Guest guest Posted October 16, 2005 Report Share Posted October 16, 2005 Namaste, Having written about Berkeley in a recent post (message # 28031), it would seem worthwhile to trace a certain thread of European thought as it progressed from Berkeley through Hume to Kant because I believe that it would give us an insight into how Consciousness stands in relation to Science, a topic that has been of some interest in the group lately. On Berkeley, I think enough has been said already, but a few words with regards to Hume would be necessary before we come to Kant's philosophical treatment of science. David Hume was the logical culmination of Berkelian Empiricism. He was also the supreme exemplar of the loss of symbolism that characterised Western Philosophy, when almost all that was once rich in Scholastic Philosophy - all the key symbols of ancient and medieval philosophy - had been masked by the darkness of the age. It was a trend that began with Descartes, and it reached its questionable 'glory' in the radical scepticism of David Hume. Hume classes all perceptions into two categories depending on "their force and vivacity" – those that are more lively he calls impressions, and those that are less lively he calls ideas. Next he says that ideas are copies of impressions. His justification for this division is based on the premise that "a blind man can form no notion of colour; a deaf man of sounds." Furthermore, he says: "Restore either of them that sense in which he is deficient; by opening this new inlet for his sensations, you also open an inlet for the ideas; and he finds no difficulty in conceiving these objects." Now the objects of human reason are again of two kinds being the relationships between ideas and the relationships between impressions. Hume says: "Of the first kind are the sciences and geometry, algebra and arithmetic, and in short, every affirmation which is either intuitively or demonstratively certain. That the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the squares of the two sides, is a proposition which expresses a relation between these figures. That three times five is equal to half of thirty, expresses a relation between these numbers. Propositions of this kind are discoverable by the mere operation of thought, without dependence on what is anywhere existent in the universe. Though there never were a circle or triangle in nature, the truths demonstrated by Euclid would for ever retain their certainty and evidence." But in so far as relations between matters of fact (i.e. between impressions) are concerned, they "are not ascertained in the same manner; nor is our evidence of their truth, however great, of a like nature with the foregoing. The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible; because it can never imply a contradiction, and is conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. That the sun will not rise tomorrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more contradiction than the affirmation, that it will rise." According to Hume, relations between ideas are perfectly determinable because they are demonstrable through ideas alone. On the other hand, relations between impressions, or matters of fact, are not thus determinable because propositions that make perfect sense may still not conform to fact, i.e., the sun will not rise tomorrow. "Nothing, at first view" says Hume "may seem more unbounded than the thought of man, which not only escapes all human power and authority, but is not even restrained within the limits of nature and reality. To form monsters, and join incongruous shapes and appearances, costs the imagination no more trouble than to conceive the most natural and familiar objects." But the relations between impressions (matters of fact) shall justifiably remain within the empirical because ideas with which we form relations are only more feeble copies of the impressions. Therefore, relations between matters of fact should be guided by the empirical. The veneration that we have for the pure sciences like mathematics are justified, but in so far as the sciences dealing with matters of fact are concerned, they need to be guided within the limits of reason. Hume observes: "all reasonings concerning matters of fact seem to be founded on the relation of cause and effect. By means of that relation alone we can go beyond the evidence of our memory or senses." Hume subjects this idea of causality to analysis. Everywhere our perception presents one sensation conjoined with another, and experiencing these compounded sensations successively we presume a 'power' within them as one determining the other and assume that the same order of relation shall prevail in the future. Behind every such assumption is the notion of a 'power' of one object to influence another – to determine or force the other to being invariably in conjunction with the first. After a detailed investigation Hume concludes that no such 'power' is empirical observed i.e., it is not an impression or matter of fact. What is it then? It is an idea that illegitimately enters into the relationship between matters of fact. Its entry is illegitimate because a legitimate idea should be a feeble copy of an impression, but here there is no causality as impression or matter of fact in order for the idea to be a legitimate valid copy i.e., when impressions do not themselves reveal the power (of cause) then it becomes illegitimate for an idea of causality to impose itself on a relationship between impressions wherein no impression of cause or 'power' reveals itself. There are merely successions of sensations. Therefore causality is illegitimate and is a mere `habit'. That, in short, is Hume. The Charvakas of India and the Pyrrhoneans of Greece would have been proud of him. And from amidst the ruins he had brought upon the great human sciences, Hume boldly declared: "When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion." Not only religion but also the sciences seemed to stand discredited. The ruins were everywhere, and there seemed to be no answer, not even from the ablest intellects of Europe. From out of this despondency there arose one man who was to change the course of European thought. His name was Immanuel Kant, and the seminal book he wrote was 'The Critique of Pure Reason'. The foundations of science were in shambles. Berkeley had shown that the world science explained was nothing but mind. Hume knocked down the pillars of causality that science was built on. The sack of science seemed complete. It was left to Kant to restore once more the dignity of science. But it is not easy to read Kant. His language is obscure and his style is difficult and verbose. What he could say in two paragraphs, he says in four chapters of convoluted language. But it is still rewarding to see how Kant saved science from the sledge- hammer of Hume's scepticism. If Berkeley had shown that the world is only mind, Kant begins by assuming that the world as we see it is rooted in the mind. He calls this the Copernican Inversion in philosophy. For experience to be possible, says Kant, the forms of all experience must lie ready a priori in the mind as the paraphernalia for experience; otherwise it is difficult to see how anything at all may be experienced. Kant derives his philosophy from these apriori forms and notions rather than from the world and therefore he calls his philosophy 'Transcendental Philosophy'. There are things that we know prior to experience, and these he calls knowledge apriori. We do not seek to derive this knowledge from experience, but impose them on to experience. Then there are things we know from experience and these he calls knowledge aposteriori. These are the forms and sensations we experience. The judgments that we make regarding our experience fall into two types: analytical and synthetical. An analytical judgment is one that does not need anything other than the object because the answer is contained in (the analytic of) the conception of the object itself. For example, the proposition that all bodies have mass does not need anything outside the conception of body to judge whether all bodies have mass because bodies are such things that have mass, i.e., there is no conception of body that does not include the conception of mass. A synthetical judgment on the other hand is one that involves two disjoint conceptions. For example, the judgment regarding the colour of a table is a synthetical judgment because the conception of a table does not involve the conception of the specific colour (say white) that it may have. Table and the colour white are two different concepts and we would have to rely on experience to inform us for making the judgment in this case. Now combining the two kinds of knowledge and the two kinds of judgment, we may further classify the kinds of judgments into four: Analytical apriori Analytical aposteriori Synthetical aposteriori Synthetical apriori Analytical apriori judgments are the domain of pure sciences like mathematics. They are true because the judgments derive their certainty from the conceptions that lie within the object to be judged. They are tautological. Analytical aposteriori judgments are redundant because they are given even before we experience them. If I see two apples and then another two apples and together see four apples, the experience merely reflects the apriori knowledge that I already have. Judgment from experience in this case is redundant. Synthetical aposteriori judgments are those that are given by experience. That a particular table is white is known only from experience. This is the empirical part of science – the experientially verifiable component. Synthetical apriori judgments are those judgments wherein two disparate conceptions are joined together apriori, for example, the proposition that every effect has a cause. This kind of knowledge is not given by the sensible impressions of experience, but yet it comprises the conception that we invariably impose on experience. How indeed may we justify these synthetical apriori judgments when they involve two or more conceptions that are not given in the field of experience? This is the vital question that Kant seeks to answer for it is the validity or invalidity of synthetical apriori judgments that make or break all our sciences (as well as religion). The sensible forms that we experience are the aesthetics of experience, the play of forms upon our senses. The investigation of sensible forms in the Transcendental Philosophy is the science of the Transcendental Aesthetic. For the experience of the transcendental aesthetic to be possible, two forms of pure intuition must exist as necessary conditions – these are space and time. But we do not merely experience forms in space and time, we also relate them one with another through reason, and in the Transcendental Philosophy the investigation of the categories of relation which bind the sensible forms of the aesthetic is the Transcendental Analytic. These are the categories substance, causality and all those concepts with which we ratiocinate experience, and which are given to experience by synthetical apriori judgments. But the question remains: How are synthetical judgments possible at all? If they are the conjunction of two concepts, how are they brought together as bearing one upon the other? Where is their binding principle? The binding principle Kant discovers in the Synthetical Unity of Consciousness. Sensible forms and causality may be different concepts, but they are found in a unity, and that unity is the unity of Consciousness. All the manifold that is found in the field of experience, and all the categories of reason, exist within the unity of conscious experience in which we behold them. Even the notion that 'I behold' lies within this unity and is given to me in the apperception of this unity, and as an analytic of the unity. It is a synthetical unity because it has within it the manifold of forms and categories of reason, but this manifold is given as separate things only through an apperception of the synthetical unity of consciousness. The categories are thus the analytic of this unity and are found as the necessary condition by which experience may be as it is. Thus, our experience, such as it is, can only be this way by virtue of these categories existing in the analytic of the unity. The binding principle of synthetical apriori judgments is the synthetical unity of consciousness. Therefore causality is valid. Science had been saved. But what saved it was Consciousness as its Ground, as the Principle that gave meanings to the things that science investigated. If science exists today with a measure of confidence, it is because its Ground is Consciousness. But what an irony of fate that today science looks to finding Consciousness in some nook and corner of the brain! The Charvakas believed that consciousness arose due to the configuration of the body. In refuting the doctrine, Sri Shankaracharya remarks that the doctrine of the Charvakas amounts to saying that a man carries himself on his own shoulder! Warm regards, Chittaranjan Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Recommended Posts
Join the conversation
You are posting as a guest. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.
Note: Your post will require moderator approval before it will be visible.