Guest guest Posted July 18, 2007 Report Share Posted July 18, 2007 a bit lengthy but a good read.. a tiny tad bit on choice and consciousness: ...The Kantian critique of the Cartesian " mirror-model " of self-consciousness depends on a particular, and limited, notion of self-inquiry: epistemology through rational introspection. We could call it rational empiricism, where reason attempts to view or reflect the " I " by objectifying it as " me, " the phenomenal self. Meanwhile, the " I " as it is in itself, remains beyond reach, an unknowable source of knowing residing transcendentally in the numenon. Kant's method of self-inquiry, though a form of introspection (reason), nevertheless analytically objectifies the ego, and thus qualifies as a third-person perspective. But there are other modes of self-inquiry that do not rely wholly on reason. Meditative and contemplative disciplines, for instance, can transcend reason and logic to arrive at deep intuitive, or noetic, knowledge--a knowing that transcends the duality of " I " and " me " (Merrell-Wolff, 1983; Forman, 1990). Kant's dichotomy, therefore, of the transcendental ego and the phenomenal ego, which posits an insurmountable divide between the objectively-known self and the unknowable transcendental " I " -in-itself, is a result of his limited empiricism and epistemology. By engaging in contemplative practices, or inner empiricism (Needleman & de Quincey, 1993) the duality of " I " and " me " can be transcended. Such inner empiricism (distinct from rational empiricism) penetrates the essence of subjectivity, and thus qualifies as first-person perspective par excellence. And there is yet a third approach to self-inquiry: intersubjective empiricism, which avoids the Kantian impossibility of the " I' reflecting itself without objectifying itself as " me. " By encountering others as loci of experiencing selves, just like our self, we can, indeed, come to know ourselves reflected in the other. Unlike the failed Cartesian one-way mirror-model of self-consciousness, the intersubjective approach involves a kind of " two-way mirror, " where not only can we " see through " to the other self, we see our own spontaneous self reflected back through them--and this experience is itself constitutive of the experiencing " I. " Part of who I am, who I experience myself to be, is formed, perhaps even created, by engaging with " you. " This was Fichte's approach, modified by Humboldt and Kierkegaard, and taken up later by Habermas. Fichte's self-positing self. Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1907) attempted to augment Kant's transcendental ego by the notion of the " self-positing self. " For Fichte, the ego creates itself through an existential act of self-choice and achieves individuality through intersubjective encounters with other egos. Its uniqueness is shaped by these encounters. Thus Fichte's existential self-positing-intersubjective ego has both transcendental and immanent aspects. It also presupposes a pre-existing self that engages other pre-existing selves. Thus Fichte's approach opens the way to account for what happens to the self-positing-self, to its forms or contents (weak/psychological intersubjectivity), but it does not advance our knowledge of consciousness or self as an ontological context (strong/philosophical intersubjectivity). Both Søren Kierkegaard and Wilhelm von Humboldt (see below) argued that Fichte's transcendental-immanent ego led to contradictions and paradoxes, and did not resolve the paralogisms of self identified by Kant. The problem, they believed, resulted from the notion of the transcendental ego. They rejected the transcendental ego altogether, and instead proposed a wholly immanent self, situated in the concrete world of life events and life histories (a view developed later, and along very different lines in John Dewey [1949], and Martin Heidegger [1978]). Kierkegaard's existential self-choice. Kierkegaard (1987) retained and reworked Fichte's notion of self-positing into an existential theory of self-choice--a self that authentically chooses its own particular life history, and thereby establishes its unique individuality. Kierkegaard's " self-choice " involves a performative rather than a descriptive concept of individuality, an idea later taken up by Jürgen Habermas (1992). In other words, when I choose myself as this person with this particular life history, and simultaneously assert and project myself into the world, what matters is not any third-person (or first-person) description of this self, but my claim to radical authenticity. Self, then, becomes not something to be described, but something to perform. The self is a claim: " I am who I am. " But as a claim, the self must then be recognized or acknowledged, accepted, or rejected by other selves--by Other. For Kierkegaard, this Other was God (Kierkegaard, 1987). Humboldt's linguistic community. Wilhelm von Humboldt took a different approach. For him, the " other " became a community of other selves, united in a linguistic system. Instead of describing the self as an individual subject, he described encounters between speakers and hearers in a linguistic community--an exchange or meeting of perspectives, acknowledging, without objectifying, each other. Instead of Kant's transcendental subject, the locus of consciousness for Humboldt was a plurality of linguistic participants and perspectives. Unity in the participating community was achieved through " unforced agreement in conversation " without canceling diversity (Habermas, 1992, p. 163). Humboldt, thus, emphasized three elements that would later be essential to Habermas' theory of communicative action: the notions of " linguistic community, " " intersubjectivity, " and " unforced agreement in dialogue. " Because of his emphasis on linguistic exchanges, Humboldt's position is a version of standard, consensual agreement, " intersubjectivity-1. " Mead's intersubjective alter egos. From Kant, through Fichte, Kierkegaard, and Humboldt, the philosophy of consciousness progressively moved away from its moorings in the Cartesian subject-object dualism and the one-way mirror-model of self-reflective consciousness. However, even with Kant's transcendental ego, Fichte's self-positing ego, Kierkegaard's existential self-choice, and Humboldt's intersubjective linguistic community, no clear path had yet emerged by which the gap between first-person " I " -subjects and third-person " it " -objects could be bridged. George Herbert Mead (1967), social psychologist and social philosopher, introduced the crucial missing element: the second-person. With this innovation, Mead made it possible for the self to know itself by mirroring itself in an " object. " But this was no ordinary third-person object; in fact, it was not an " object " at all. It was another self--a second-person, alter ego. Instead of the epistemological contortions of a first-person " I " attempting to adopt the third-person perspective of an external observer of itself, the self becomes known through the interactions of first-person and second-person perspectives of participants in active linguistic communication. Now, the self is not mirrored as an object from a third-person perspective, but as communicating egos mutually reflecting each other. My self, then, is perceived as the alter ego to your alter ego. I am " other, " as a self, to you as another self: an encounter of mutually-acknowledging selves. I perceive you as a subject in the second-person, and " me " as your subject in the second person. From the second-person view, who I am--the self I experience myself to be--is shaped, or informed, by being with you. Given this circle of intersubjectivity, of mutually participant subjects engaged in linguistic communication, how do we account for individual subjects? Underlying the " intersubjective project " --common to theorists from Mead and Buber to Habermas--is a motivation to not only counteract the exaggerated subjectivist bias in philosophy of consciousness, but also to avoid swamping the individual in overwhelming social norms of the collective, thereby depriving the individualized person of his or her autonomy and spontaneity. Intersubjectivity aims to create a middle course between the extremes of Cartesian subjectivism and Marxist collectivism (Voloshinov, 1996). But if, as Mead argues, the self shows up only in the linguistic circle of intersubjectivity how do we account for the individual subjects that intersubjectivity would seem to presuppose? How can there be a circle of intersubjectivity unless there are subjects already present to start with? Mead recognized this problem and proposed as a solution that in the same moment the self encounters an alter ego-the moment " I " encounter " you " -the concrete organism establishes a relationship to itself. " The self, as that which can be an object to itself, is essentially a social structure, and it arises in social experience " (Mead, 1962, p. 140). The self is thus " first encountered as a subject in the moment when communicative relations are established between organisms. " (Hohengarten, 1992, p. xvi). The self, thus, has two components: the theoretical " me, " my consciousness of myself, and the practical " me, " the agency through which I monitor my behavior (such as speaking). " The 'I' is the response of the organism to the attitudes of the others; the 'me' is the organized set of attitudes of others which one himself assumes " (Mead, 1962, p. 175). Hohengarten explains: This practical " me " comes into existence when the subject establishes a practical relation to herself by adopting the normative attitude of an alter ego toward her own behavior. . . . such a conventionally constituted self is nonetheless a precondition for the emergence of a nonconventional aspect of the practical self: the practical " I, " which opposes the " me " with both presocial drives and innovative fantasy. . .. . Yet the self is intersubjectively constituted through and through; the relationship to a community is what makes the practical relation-to-self possible (Hohengarten, 1992, pp. xvi-xvii. Italics added). Mead's emphasis on the intersubjective constitution of the self, of the subject's sense of continuity and identity, accounts for self as an " individualized context " for the contents of experience. But it still does not account for the " metacontext " --the non-individualized ontological context that underlies all contents of consciousness. Mead's " self, " although a context for contents of individual experience, is itself a content within the ontological metacontext of consciousness-as-such. Mead's intersubjectivity still leaves unexplained ontological subjectivity--the fact that at least some loci in the universal matrix have a capacity for interiority, for a what-it-feels-like from within. It would still be possible, in Mead's theory, for a universe consisting wholly of objects to produce, via linguistic and social relations, what he calls " intersubjectivity. " But this could logically be an " intersubjectivity " without any interiority, without any true subjectivity (in other words, intersubjectivity-1)--and therefore not truly intersubjectivity (as defined here) at all. Buber's 'I and Thou.' Probably the theorist most readily associated with the notion of intersubjectivity (as a mutual engagement of interior presences) is the philosopher-anthropologist and theologian Martin Buber (1878-1965). As he himself acknowledged, he picked up the germ of the idea, in 1843, from the philosopher of religion Ludwig Feuerbach: " The individual man does not contain in himself the essence of man either in so far as he is a moral being or in so far as he is a thinking being. The essence of man is contained only in the community, in the unity of man and man-a unity which rests upon the reality of the difference between 'I' and 'Thou' " (Quoted by Gabriel Marcel, in Buber, 1967, p. 42). Feuerbach, however, did not pursue the idea, and Buber's priority, rightly, rests on the fact that he devoted his professional career, and a long list of works, to developing the implications of Feuerbach's revolutionary insight. For Buber, Feuerbach's insight was comparable to the Copernican revolution, opening up new vistas in understanding about the nature of human beings, and not only with profound epistemological relevance but also ontologically revealing. In Buber's hands, these implications were worked out in great detail (1961; 1965; 1970). Specifically, the essence of human being was relationship, and Buber gave ontological status to the " between " --a mysterious force, " presence, " or creative milieu, in which the experience of being a self arises. Relations, then, not the relata, were primordial, if not actually primary. " Spirit is not in the I but between I and You " (Buber, 1970, p. 89). Only when " I " respond to " you, " a fellow locus of presence or spirit, does my own being transcend the " oppressive force which emanates from objects " (Marcel, 1967). According to Buber, human beings have two responses available to the world: to relate to what is present either as an object ( " I-it " relationship) or as another responsible being ( " I-thou relationship). When we engage with the " other " as I-thou, relationship is mutually co-creating. The ontological status of the relationship, the " between, " is emphasized by Buber when he refers to I-thou as " one word, " representing a fundamental human reality of mutuality. Buber's claim that a concrete reality may be related to as either an " it " or a " thou " raises some profound implications for philosophy of mind-particularly the issue of " other minds. " As Charles Hartshorne (1967) observed, there are at least three options available if we choose to relate to some creature as a " thou " : (1) animistically, as a sentient and perhaps conscious individual, with a " soul " of its own (animistic-panpsychism); (2) as part of, or a manifestation of, such an individual, such as some member of a " cosmic organism " (e.g. Plotinian emanationist idealism, or Spinozistic monism); or (3) as a collection, or unity, of sentient, experiencing individuals (panexperientialism). Science is incapable of determining whether any of these options is valid (we lack a " Chalmers' consciousness meter " ); Buber's " I-thou " relationship may well extend beyond human interactions. Epistemologically, empirical validation of consciousness would require a major shift to the kind of radical empiricism advocated by William James (1977)--where all contents of experience (and only those), not just sense-mediated data, are legitimate data for a science of consciousness. It would require also a radical ontology that allows for the intrinsic reality of consciousness or experience all the way down (de Quincey, 1994). The process philosophies of both Hartshorne (1991) and A. N. Whitehead (1979), advocating a panpsychist or panexperientialist ontology, are deeply compatible with this aspect of Buber's vision-replacing the notion of substance with dynamic relations. However, Buber is not always consistent about whether the relationship, the " betweenness, " is fundamental, or whether, as logic seems to require, any relationship must always be between some pre-existing entities. Philip Wheelwright (1967, p. 75) sums up Buber's position in Between Man and Man, which appears to support this latter view: " By nature each person is a single being, finding himself in company with other single beings; to be single is not to be isolated, however, and by vocation each one is to find and realize his proper focus by entering into relationship with others. " Jacques' Tripartite Intersubjectivity. The primacy of relations, of intersubjectivity, becomes most explicit in the more recent work of Francis Jacques-perhaps the leading contemporary dialogue philosopher and linguist in France. His self-proclaimed project is to " found the conception of subjectivity on relations between persons . . . treating the relation as a primordial reality, a reality which constitutes one of the very conditions of possibility of meaning and which is prior even to I and you " (Jacques, 1991, p. xii). For Jacques, as for Habermas, " the self is a function of the communicative interaction which occurs in dialogue " (1991). Jacques has developed a theory of " being-as-speaking " and of the " being-who-speaks. " He parts company with most other intersubjectivists, by presenting a tripartite schema of the subject--not just " I " and " thou, " but one that includes also " he/she. " Self-identity, he says, results from integration of the three poles of any communication: " by speaking to other and saying I, by being spoken to by others as you, or by being spoken of by others as a he/she that the subject would accept as appropriate " (Jacques, 1991, p. xv). He takes issue with Buber who claimed that human beings become I and derive their interiority only when they encounter a you. Jacques argues that a human being becomes a personal self only when, in addition to I-thou, the " otherness " of an absent third-party, he/she, is acknowledged. Besides the I and you, self-identity requires " taking account of the third person and integrating it into the identificational process . . . For when one speaks of someone else, he/she is not the same as it--a point that neither Buber nor Gabriel Marcel, nor Levinas appreciated " (Jacques, 1991 p. xv). Jacques' main point may be encapsulated in the paradoxical notion of " presence of absence " --the felt presence of the departed other as an indispensable constituent of the sense of self. The absent third-party (not to be confused with third-person it) does not stand outside the intersubjective or interlocutive process. The other person is simply not present in the moment of dialogue, but has a decisive influence nonetheless. Just think, for instance, how even an absent spouse or boss hovers in the background of many conversations. In a paradoxical way, their absence is a felt presence. Jacques, with his tripartite interlocutive model of self-identity, has addressed head-on the subject-object " impasse " characteristic of modern philosophy of consciousness. In a comparable way, though from a different angle, Jürgen Habermas has developed a thoroughgoing intersubjectivity based on the centrality of language to consciousness. I will now spend a little more time on Habermas than I have on other theorists because, I believe, Habermas is arguably the most influential contemporary philosopher for whom the idea of intersubjectivity is central to his work. I will also explain why, despite Habermas' immensely valuable contribution to second-person, dialogic philosophy, his version of " intersubjectivity, " relying on linguistic communities, still falls short of intersubjectivity as " engaged presence. " Habermas: Language and Consciousness Building on Mead's view of the subject in Mind, Self & Society, and incorporating developmental ideas from Piaget and Kohlberg, Jürgen Habermas emphasizes that the process of individuation of the self depends on the development of a postconventional identity--a subject who simultaneously is shaped in intersubjective communicative action and who transcends the otherwise binding norms of that linguistic society. Although the claim of radical authenticity depends on the recognition (though not necessarily the acceptance) of others, by the imaginative act of projecting a " universal community of all possible alter egos " the subject authentically retains autonomy-remaining a true subject within a creative web of intersubjectivities: The idealizing supposition of a universalistic form of life, in which everyone can take up the perspective of everyone else and can count on reciprocal recognition by everybody, makes it possible for individuated beings to exist within a community--individualism as the flip-side of universalism (Habermas, 1992, p. 186). Habermas is pre-eminently concerned with the role of language in shaping who we are as human beings. But his concern is not limited to an analysis of the structure or grammar of language, to its propositional content--he is not a linguistic analyst. Habermas is concerned with the real-world speaking of language, to its impact on who we take ourselves to be, and on how we act in the world. He is hardly interested in the theory of language, but is emphatically concerned with the practice of language--with its performative function. Language engages speakers and hearers in such a way that both participate and risk themselves in communication. In the process, consciousness intersubjectively creates and reveals itself. We can identify three central elements of Habermas' work--the three " Ps " : (1) emphasis on practice away from theory; (2) the public or intersubjective origin and role of language and meaning; and (3) the performative function of language. From Theory to Practice. Habermas is concerned to show that philosophy, to have any value and meaning, must engage with the world. Abstractions without the meat and muscle of practical action are little more than intellectual self-indulgence. Such philosophy can do nothing for us. In this earlier phase of his work, Habermas displays the deep influence of Western Marxism in his thought and political engagement. (Habermas was active in German student political action in the Sixties.) The Public Sphere. Later, Habermas reveals what has become a consistent theme throughout all his work: that language is first and foremost a public or social enterprise. At this stage, Habermas' central concern is political rather than philosophical (although in his work the two are never far apart). His focus is on working out an intellectual and practical basis for public discourse so that everyone, not just the bourgeois elite, would participate in effective control of public policy. Communicative Action. Implicit in his political stance of discourse in the public sphere is a philosophical insight that he later made far more explicit: Meaning is not dependent on the grammatical structures or private " monological " subjective intentions of a speaker's language; meaning is derived from interaction of intersubjective communication. Language and meaning unfold from the " dialogical " reciprocity of " I-speakers " and " you-listeners. " The two most dominant influences on Habermas here are pioneer linguist-philosopher Wilhelm von Humboldt and philosopher-psychologist George Herbert Mead. Language and meaning are products of the " public sphere, " not the creation of individual, lone-operating subjects. Habermas' central concern is to argue that all language involves a performative function. That is, language does not merely describe the world but engages the subject with the world through the listener. Intersubjective Meaning. While Habermas agrees that meaning cannot be understood independently of the conditions of its occurrence, he denies that these conditions are determined exclusively by structures of power and dominance, as claimed by deconstructive postmodernists. Instead, Habermas argues, the conditions for " interpretant relations " (that is, meaning) are dependent on conditions of intersubjective communication oriented toward mutual understanding. This is a picture of language relations, and the consequent role of reason, very different from that of postmodernists such as Derrida (1967) and Foucault (1970). Instead of individual and separate subjects engaged in interminable power struggles, Habermas' theory of communicative action refers to communities of subjects who partially create each other, and therefore strive for mutual understanding. Reasoning, thus, becomes a public enterprise. In Postmetaphysical Thinking, Habermas observes that language performs three distinct, but intimately and invariably interconnected, functions: (1) a speaker comes to an understanding with (2) another person about (3) something in the world. In turn, these three functions of language correspond to three types of validity claims. In Habermas' theory, meaning is not a product of any " picture theory of language " (as early Wittgenstein believed in the Tractatus); it is not a description of a correspondences between words and facts or states of affairs. There is no independent subject unilaterally turning out " word pictures " that match some objective reality. Nor is meaning a matter of Humpty-Dumptyesque arbitrary choosing what words mean. Nor is meaning an indefinite and indeterminate deferral of différance, forever sliding beyond reach, so that nothing really has any meaning at all (as Derrida and his deconstructionist followers would have it). Rather, says Habermas, meaning is constituted in the shared speech-acts of a communicating community of mutual-determining, uncoerced subjects. Language, then, on this view, is a pragmatic, holistic act. Its smallest unit is not some disembodied or abstract sign, word or phoneme, but an utterance that involves three mutually interacting components--the speaker, the hearer, and the world in which they are situated. Each language utterance, or speech act, is like a token that the speaker offers to a listener (or community of listeners). This " token " expresses an experience of the world claimed to be true, right, and sincere by the speaker, and it may be either rejected or accepted by the hearer. In either case, the validity claims of " true, " " right, " and " sincere " can be tested by the community of speakers and hearers. It is here, in Habermas, where " intersubjective agreement " (through linguistic tokens) and " intersubjective co-creativity " (through shared experience) come together. The first is a foundation for consensual scientific knowledge established between communicating individual subjects (Velmans, 1992). The second is true intersubjective mutual beholding--where the experience of self, of consciousness, arises as a felt experience from the encounter. A final quote from Habermas sums up his intersubjective position: The ego, which seems to me to be given in my self-consciousness as what is purely my own, cannot be maintained by me solely through my own power, as it were for me alone--it does not " belong " to me. Rather, this ego always retains an intersubjective core because the process of individuation from which it emerges runs through the network of linguistically mediated interactions (Habermas, 1992, p. 170). The Missing Perspective: Why Intersubjectivity is Transparent In this paper, I have introduced key ideas of a handful of philosophers who have attempted to focus on what I take to be a conspicuous oversight in Western philosophy in general and in philosophy of mind in particular. With these few exceptions--such as psychologist George Herbert Mead, theologian Martin Buber, and contemporary scholars such as Jürgen Habermas in Germany and Francis Jacques in France--I know of no philosopher in the Western tradition who has systematically approached the problem of subject-world relation, and particularly the question of consciousness, by invoking the second-person perspective as an alternative to the first-person perspective of subjectivists and idealists, and the third-person perspective of the objectivists and materialists. (5) Because of his inclusion of the " interior-social (cultural) " in his detailed four-quadrants model, Ken Wilber (1995) should also be included as a scholar who recognizes the importance of dialogic relationship in any comprehensive study of consciousness. However, unlike Habermas, Jacques, Buber, or Mead, intersubjectivity is not a central concern for Wilber. The standard approaches to the study of consciousness have bifurcated along apparently irreconcilable methodologies derived, respectively, from Cartesian-inspired philosophy of the subject (first-person epistemology) and from Hobbesian-inspired philosophy of matter (third-person objects). In the first case, knowledge of the objective world remains problematic; in the second, knowledge of the knowing subject (of consciousness)--and therefore of all knowledge--is inexplicable and radically problematic. Hardly anyone, it seems, in philosophy of mind has been drawn to approach the study of consciousness from a second-person perspective (of mutually engaged subjects). For a long time, I have wondered why there is this glaring omission. We all use all three ways of knowing--objectivity, subjectivity, and intersubjectivity--in one form or another most of the time. We all deal with external material objects, we all feel what it is like to be a being from within, and we all participate and communicate with other human beings. But whereas, for centuries, both objectivity and subjectivity have been investigated as ways of knowing in Western science and philosophy, intersubjectivity has been ignored for the most part--particularly with reference to exploration of consciousness. Why? I wonder if this oversight is an example of a " fish-in-water " syndrome. We tend not to notice the second-person perspective because it is right in front of our noses everyday. It's the medium in which we most naturally live. Whereas for third-person perspective we need to set up controlled (and artificial) laboratory experiments to induce (at least the illusion of) a separation between observer and observed, and thus step back, or step out of the stream of natural living and human interaction. This stepping-back allows us to notice the third-person perspective in action--because it's not " normal. " Similarly, for first-person perspective: in meditation (or other contemplative or introspective) disciplines we " withdraw " from the " normal " world, and the subjective perspective shows up in contrast. But normal day-to-day living, interacting with and encountering other people, is the usual medium for consciousness; the mutuality of shared-perspective is at least available to us throughout the day in every encounter (even if we actually rarely consciously engage in it). Like first- and third-person perspectives, the second-person perspective can be another mode of conscious inquiry--where consciousness (and the reality that consciousness reveals) can be investigated as a process of mutual " taking account of " the other(s). Something different happens in consciousness when we engage like this. Physicist David Bohm recognized this potential for consciousness exploration in his approach to " dialogue " (Bohm, 1985; 1996). Clearly, our language already presents us with three, not just two, options-first, second, and third-person pronouns, " I, " " you, " and " it. " And the second-person perspective, both theoretically and experientially (that is, pragmatically), is a logical and natural bridge between the apparent dichotomy of the knowing subject and the world of objects--between " I " and " it, " between interior " I " and exterior " other. " When I communicate with you, particularly in a face-to-face encounter, something about who I am and something about the world shows up through you--and vice versa. The " I " that encounters you (as the locus of another " I " ) is different from the " I " that encounters the world as a conglomeration of " its. " Who I am can be revealed (at least partially) through my encounter with you, whereas I-as- " I " remain entirely unattainable if I encounter the world as merely a collection of " its. " I (as subject) am never reflected in things (objects), only in other " I " s such as you. The " I " that can show up as an object either in first-person introspection as " me, " or in third-person analysis (as in standard materialist philosophy of mind and psychology) is never truly " I " (as experiential subject) but only " me " or " it " as spatio-temporal object. There is something about the nature of consciousness, it seems, that requires the presence of the " other " as another subject that can acknowledge my being. (When I experience myself being experienced by you, my experience of myself--and of you--is profoundly enriched, and, in some encounters, even " transformed. " ) What is intriguing about Habermas' philosophy is that it is precisely this missing component of the second-person that is central to his work. Whereas Habermas restricts this " other " to what can be communicated through human language-i.e., " you " would have to be another human being--I remain open to the Whiteheadian possibility that all organisms are centers of subjectivity and therefore available to me as " I-thou " partners, not only as objective " its. " Although I am sure the quality of human-human intersubjectivity is significantly different from human-nonhuman intersubjectivity. Nevertheless, Habermas' emphasis on the intersubjective nature of language and consciousness strikes me as a major step forward, and may, more than Wittgenstein's or Heidegger's linguistic moves, lead Western philosophy, finally, beyond the perennial dualisms of subject-object, and mind-matter, providing a philosophical agenda for a science of consciousness that includes a second-person perspective to complement third- and first-person perspectives. Having surveyed a few pioneers in intersubjectivity, and outlined some of their reasons for exploring the second-person perspective, I will now outline my own theoretical perspective on the role and significance of intersubjectivity in the evolution of consciousness. Intersubjectivity and Evolution of Consciousness The Original Meaning of Consciousness The Oxford English Dictionary identifies seven varieties of consciousness (Natsoulas, 1983; Hunt, 1995), which I've summarized in the mnemonic SAIPRUD-consciousness as: (1) sentience, (2) awake/awareness, (3) interpersonal, (4) personal, (5) reflective, (6) unitive, and (7) dissociative. All varieties reveal a common characteristic, subjectivity--they are known from " within. " And, with one notable exception, all are private--the privileged domain of the individual knower. The exception is Cinterpersonal because it means " knowing or sharing the knowledge of something together with an other " (Hunt, 1995). What is interesting about this is that it is actually the form of consciousness that originally gave rise to the very concept itself--conscientia, meaning " knowing with " others (Güzeldere, 1995). It reveals that, originally, the word " consciousness " implied a dialogic process--an interaction or communication between two or more knowing beings. To be conscious meant that two or more people were privy to some item of knowledge not available to others outside the privileged circle. In this sense, " consciousness " is similar to " conspire " (to " breathe with " others). " Consciousness " meant that the privileged circle of knowers knew that each of their conspirators knew, too. Consciousness, therefore, originally implied a " shared secret " or " knowledge of a privileged few. " Consciousness, in other words, was originally communal, a property of the group. This sense remains today in forms of consciousness referred to, for example, as " social consciousness, " " political consciousness, " " feminist consciousness, " " racial consciousness, " and is manifested in such diverse groups as church congregations, religious movements, political parties, sports teams and fans, and religious and political cults. Such forms of " social consciousness " imply changes in beliefs of social groups, rather than of individual people. " Social consciousness " essentially refers to the contents of consciousness--only this time on a large scale within a community, rather than in one person. However, since it still deals with contents--with changes in consciousness at the level of groups-it is still a form of " psychological " consciousness (we might call it " psycho-social " consciousness). " Social consciousness " often masks the deeper, metaphysical, intersubjective nature of consciousness--the very condition that allows for any individual or social form of consciousness to emerge in the first place. (6) Intersubjectivity and Interpersonal Consciousness In the previous section I noted that " consciousness " originally meant to " know with " others--it was interpersonal or intersubjective. However, I now want to unpack this claim, and propose some further subtle distinctions that may help clarify why we may now have an opportunity to explore intersubjectivity in a way that was not available to our predecessors. These distinctions will borrow a concept central to Ken Wilber's critique of the evolution of consciousness in Sex, Ecology, Spirituality (1995). Wilber argues that it is a fallacy to equate " pre-egoic " consciousness (or self)--as in the so-called participation mystique of animistic worldviews--with " trans-egoic " consciousness of mystical experience. There is an evolutionary progression, Wilber argues, from pre-egoic, through various stages of egoic, to trans-egoic consciousness. And it is a serious category mistake to equate (confuse or conflate) the " pre " with the trans. " Similarly, the SAIPRUD mnemonic of varieties of consciousness I introduced earlier may be viewed as an evolutionary sequence-from consciousness as Sentience, Awake, Interpersonal, Personal, Reflexive, to Unitive. (D, dissociative, is a pathology that may occur at any stage in the process; for this reason, it may be better to write the mnemonic " SAIPRU(D). " ) In this model, it is clear that interpersonal consciousness precedes personal consciousness--intersubjectivity is prior to subjectivity, it is " pre. " This accords with the position implicit in Buber and explicit in Jacques and Habermas. However, taking a cue from Wilber's " pre/trans " distinction, I want now to distinguish between " intersubjective " and " interpersonal. " If, as claimed, subjectivity (i.e. experienced interiority) is the essential, key characteristic of consciousness, then it is present throughout the entire spectrum of consciousness, from raw sentience to mystical unity. And if, following Buber, Mead, Jacques, and Habermas, we take relations as ontologically primary, then subjectivity is always embedded within a matrix or context of mutually co-creating intersubjectivities. Thus, even at the level of raw sentience, (be it an embryo, a worm, bacterium, atom, or electron), intersubjective interiority (what-it-feels-like to be that entity) is ontologically fundamental; similarly all the way up, through consciousness-as-awake to unitive consciousness. Thus, if Cinterpersonal is present throughout, it no longer serves as a useful distinction--or indeed, a valid stage--in the evolutionary progression. It is not a stage; it is a condition of all stages. So, our mnemonic, minus Cinterpersonal, would now read: " SAPRU(D). " However, this model is incomplete: It does not account for interpersonal dialogic consciousness. But now let's revisit the " pre/trans " distinction from the perspective of the evolution of " individual self. " Historically, the notion of the " individual " as an autonomous self that could separate from the collective or community is itself an evolutionary phenomenon. Prior to the time of Alexander the Great, from Homer down to Aristotle, the " individual " was identified with the group or city-state (Tarnas, 1991; Onians, 1994). At this stage consciousness was pre-personal (Wilber's " pre-egoic " ), pre-individualized self. Thus, although intersubjectivity was present, its character was still " pre. " Consciousness as " knowing with " was group consciousness, where members of the group had little or no sense of individual self-identity. Their identity was with the tribe or group (Jaynes, 1976; Crook, 1980; de Quincey, 1995). But following the great unification of the Hellenistic world during and after Alexander's time, the uniformity of the empire made it possible and practicable for individual members to leave their city-state, for example to travel from Athens to Alexandria. The way was opened up for a detachable, individual self that could move around the empire. Result: the birth of the individual. Only then could consciousness evolve to the stage of personal consciousness (de Quincey, 1995). I now want to propose a similar model (or extension of this same model) for the emergence of trans-personal intersubjective consciousness. Just as it was almost impossible for the average citizen prior to Alexander's empire to experience individual self-identity (pre-personal)--they just didn't notice the personal quality of consciousness embedded in the group--it has been almost impossible for the average individual in contemporary society to experience intersubjectivity at the level of transpersonal consciousness. Until now (and perhaps even still), we have been too embedded in our personal consciousness, in our Cartesian-Enlightenment individualism, to notice that the deeper reality or grounding of our consciousness is the intersubjective matrix of interdependent relationships. I'm proposing that a crucial aspect of the oft-announced " new paradigm " --a worldview of nonlocal interdependence--may be the emergence of transpersonal awareness of our deep intersubjective nature. Elements or facets of this emerging worldview would include, for example, the discovery of nonlocality in quantum physics (Albert, 1992); accumulating documentation of evidence for nonlocal psi phenomena (Schlitz & Braud, 1997); increased globalization of economies (Korten, 1995); awareness of ecological interdependence (Roszak, 1992); and, perhaps, even the globalization and interconnectedness of communications technologies such as satellite TV, telephones, and the Internet (Elgin, 1993; Russell, 1995). It is becoming less and less easy to deny our deep interconnectedness. We might also include in this list a growing awareness of the central doctrine of co-dependent arising in Buddhism, as it continues to spread into modernist, Western societies and worldviews (Macy, 1991). I am proposing, therefore, that interpersonal consciousness evolves out of a prior personal consciousness. As a transpersonal mode of consciousness, it involves not only awareness of the prior personal and of the emergent interpersonal but also of the ontological grounding (or context) of all consciousness which is intersubjective. So now we have: " 'I'-SAPRIU(D) " : o Intersubjective (primordial condition and foundation for consciousness shared between all intersubjects--what many traditions refer to as " spirit " ); o Sentience (primitive capacity for feeling and self-motion in any individual organism); o Awake/awareness (higher form of sentience where organism can be either conscious or unconscious, awake or asleep); o Personal (individualized awareness with a sense of self-identity); o Reflective (capacity for self to be " aware that I am aware " --gateway to altered states of consciousness: " aware that I am aware that I am aware . . . " ): o Interpersonal (gateway to transpersonal consciousness, involving awareness not only of personal identity, but also of deep intersubjective foundation of all consciousness); o Unitive (integrates all prior forms of consciousness into experienced unity); o Dissociative (pathological failure to integrate prior forms of consciousness). According to this view, intersubjectivity is not, strictly speaking, a variety, or a state or level of consciousness like the other seven. It is the context or condition for all varieties of consciousness, and permeates the entire evolutionary spectrum. As consciousness evolves, it eventually becomes aware of this context. Csentience and Cawake are pre-personal, Cpersonal and Creflexive are personal, with Cinterpersonal evolving out of Cpersonal, emerging as the first stage in transpersonal consciousness. The integration of all stages from Csentience to Cinterpersonal is unitive consciousness. ( " D, " as before, represents the potential for dissociation at any stage, the pathological shadow side of intersubjective consciousness that prevents unitive consciousness.) Conclusion Methodological Implications of a Second-Person Perspective How does one access the second person perspective? In other words, how to tell the difference between relating to " you " and relating to an " object " --or how to persuade someone else of the difference? This is tricky. If someone doesn't " feel it, " then no amount of ostensive argument is going to win that person over. I can point all I like, but if the referent I'm pointing at just isn't available for that person, then it will seem to be an " empty set " to them. I've tried to point to the most obvious distinction that I take to be a likely element in just about everyone's experiential set: namely the experience of love, of being in love. I can't really believe that any reader of this paper has never felt the difference I'm pointing at between an intimate (love-relationship) and a non-intimate one (say, a next-door neighbor, or the local shopkeeper). That's the kind of difference I'm pointing at when I speak of " engaged presence. " The difference, however, is not absolute; it is graded on a continuum. It is possible to have a second-person experience with the neighbor or shopkeeper. What matters is our willingness and ability to acknowledge and be open to the presence of the other as a locus of experience that can reciprocate that acknowledgment. We can interact with the shopkeeper (and, indeed, with a lover) mechanically and habitually without experiencing them as a reciprocating center of experience (many of us do this more than we'd care to admit)--or we can interact intersubjectively. The experiential difference is dramatic. Unfortunately, I can no more give a prescription for how to do this than I can for how to fall in love. But I trust that the ability is innate. This does not mean, however, that there is no methodology we can use to facilitate second-person inquiry--we just cannot guarantee the methodology will work in every case, every time. The procedure I have found to be most conducive to this kind of intersubjective experience is the form of dialogue developed by David Bohm (1985; 1986). Numerous tapes, books, and articles are available, as well as practicum courses and meetings, where any interested inquirer can learn and practice this method of dialogue (Gerard & Teurfs, 1994). A description of the parameters of Bohmian dialogue would be out of place in this article. I think it is sufficient to let readers know a " recipe " is available; they must " bake the cake " for themselves. Fewer things are as dry and as uninspiring as a step-by-step procedure for how to attain a particular experience. If you want to experience the joys of sex--go do it. Similarly, if you are interested in researching intersubjectivity, follow the procedure for yourself. Any interested reader can take the necessary steps to learn the methodology. From Mechanism to Meaning How might the philosophical approach to second-person perspective discussed here translate into a science of consciousness--resulting in a body of empirical data and testable hypotheses? Methodologically, how might it differ from first- or third-person perspectives? As we have seen, the most obvious difference is that the intersubjective approach would involve two or more people committedly engaged in the presence of the other(s)-an epistemology of presence (Ha'iri Yazdi, 1992). It is the difference between an " I-it " relationship (third-person) and " I-me " relationship (first-person) and " I-you " (second-person). In this last case, consciousness is experienced truly as " intersubjective " and transpersonal, that is, transcending the individual Cartesian subject. Loosely, we might say it occurs " somewhere between and enveloping " the participants (recognizing, of course, the use of the spatial " somewhere " and " enveloping " are just metaphors). The point is that consciousness " shows up " as a co-creativity between or among the participants. The implications range from, in philosophy, prompting us to reconsider our basic ontology--from discrete physical substances to a more process-oriented relational ontology of interpenetrating experiences (as in Whitehead, 1979), to, in philosophy and science, providing a different way to approach the problem of other minds, or even possibly elucidating the mystery of parapsychological phenomena. As an epistemology of " presence, " second-person intersubjectivity, opens the way to a deep exploration of relationship--an approach that could take science beyond epistemology of objects, beyond methodologies of objectivity, measurement and quantification, beyond a preoccupation with mechanisms. As in first-person methodologies, the emphasis in second-person science would be on engagement rather than measurement, meaning rather than mechanism. Explanations in terms of mechanism are inappropriate for consciousness and mental phenomena because mechanisms involve exchanges of energy. They can provide explanations only of objective, physical things and processes. Where consciousness is involved, where subjective, interior experience is concerned, connections occur through shared meaning, not physical mechanisms. Thus, instead of third-person explanations in terms of physical causes and effects, consciousness invites us to look for understanding or insight in terms of intersubjective, shared participation in the meanings of things and their relationships--and in the meaning of the world as a whole. In conclusion: We could say that standard third-person inquiry leads to a science of external bodies, first-person inquiry to an interior science of the mind, while second-person engagement leads to a communal science of the heart. Whereas the ultimate ideal of objective knowledge is control, and the ultimate ideal of subjective knowledge is peace, the ultimate ideal of intersubjective knowledge is relationship--and, dare I say it, love. Notes 1. Socrates' method of engaged questioning, which by-passed the normal rational, cognitive faculties, was directed at the soul or essence of the other person-a process that often left the other person with a feeling of great discomfort, and sometimes of transformation. Socrates was a master at penetrating behind perceptual and emotional surfaces to the deeper, core " presence " of the other person. To be in dialogue with Socrates was to find your precious opinions and certainties based on appearances dismantled and shattered-to discover some deeper truth about yourself. See, for example, the famous encounter between Socrates and the slave boy in the Meno, where by a process of engaged questioning, Socrates draws out of the uneducated slave a " recollection " of knowledge of geometry that the boy didn't know he knew. 2. This distinction between philosophical and psychological meanings of consciousness is not to imply that psychologists do not concern themselves with philosophical issues of consciousness, nor that philosophers do not concern themselves with psychological issues. Clearly, there is much overlap between disciplines. Some philosophers do investigate mental acts and contents, not to mention issues of perception and sensation, and some psychologists are interested in the ontological status of consciousness. Nevertheless, the distinction remains useful because, for the most part, psychologists concern themselves with consciousness as a state of awareness contrasted with the unconscious, while philosophers (particularly philosophers of mind), for the most part, concern themselves with consciousness as a state of being contrasted with non-consciousness. The essential point is that the distinction " consciousness vs. unconscious " is psychological (the " unconscious " is a psychological/psychoanalytical concept), and the distinction " consciousness vs. nonconsciousness " is ontological, and, therefore, philosophical ( " nonconsciousness, " the complete absence of any mental activity whatsoever, is an ontological/philosophical issue). A more accurate, though less elegant, way to address this distinction would be to compare " psychological/epistemological " meanings of consciousness with " philosophical/ontological " meanings of consciousness. 3. Wilber's treatment of intersubjectivity, however--echoing the sociolinguistics of theorists such as Humbolt, Mead, and Habermas--tends to restrict it to the weakest form (intersubjectivity-1) that relies on the exchange of linguistic tokens (physical signals), and does not emphasize the nonphysical experience of shared presence that is central to actual intersubjective communion (intersubjectivity 2a and 2b). 4. Joseph Prabhu, professor of philosophy and religion at California State University drew my attention to the " dialogue philosophers, " particularly Rozenzweig and Rosenstock-Huessy, and to the relevance of Dewey's and Taylor's discussions of the social context for self. 5. In the Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 1996, two authors Piet Hut, an astrophysicist, and Roger Shepard, a psychologist, included second-person perspective as a possible angle on the " explanatory gap " between brain and mind. In " Turning the hard problem upside down and sideways. " They addressed, a second-person point of view in a couple of paragraphs, but did not develop this line of inquiry. Nonetheless, their paper does demonstrate that the idea of second-person study of consciousness is already " in the air. " They noted, " The fact that we can and do interact with others is an aspect of conscious experience that is at least as important as the possibility that we humans have of reflecting on our own experience. " 6. We have many examples of " expanding or changing social consciousness " -e.g. in feminism, new age movements, ethnic diversity, ecological awareness. But these are not the most interesting cases facing a science of consciousness. These kinds of changes have happened throughout human history. What has never happened (at least not in modern, Western society) is the development of a true science of consciousness that can explore the world of mind with the same degree of rigor we have so far used to explore the world of matter. References Aboulafia, M. (1986), The mediating self: Mean, Sartre, and self-determination. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Albert, D. Z. (1992), Quantum mechanics and experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Arens, E. (1994), The logic of pragmatic thinking: From Peirce to Habermas (trans. David Smith). New Jersey: Humanities Press. Bakhtin, M. (1981), The dialogic imagination: Four essays by M. M. Bakhtin (trans. M. Holquist). Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Benveniste, E. (1973), Problems in general linguistics. Miami, FL: University of Miami Press. Binswanger, L. (1963), Being-in-the-world: Selected papers of Ludwig Binswanger (trans. with introduction by Jacob Needleman). New York: Harper & Row. Binswanger, L. (1986), Dream and existence: Michel Foucault & Ludwig Binswanger (ed. by Keith Hoeller). Seattle, WA: Review of Existential Psychology & Psychiatry. (Originally published in Binswanger, 1963.) Bohm, D. (1985), Unfolding meaning: A weekend of dialogue. London, UK: Routledge. Buber, M. (1961), Between man and man (trans. R. G. Smith). London, UK: Collins/Fontana. Buber, M. (1965), The knowledge of man: Selected essays (ed. Maurice Friedman). New York: Harper & Row. Buber, M. (1967), The philosophy of Martin Buber (ed. Paul A. Schlipp). La Salle, IL: Open Court. Buber, M. (1970), I and thou. New York: Charles Scribners Sons. Crook, J. (1980), The evolution of human consciousness. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. Derrida, J. (1967), Of grammatology (trans. G. C. Spivak). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press. Dewey, J. (1949) Experience and nature. New York: Macmillan. de Quincey, C. (1994), " Consciousness all the way down? An analysis of McGinn's critique of panexperientialism. " Journal of Consciousness Studies, 1(2), 217-229. de Quincey, C. (1995), " Transformation of Western Consciousness. " (Unpublished manuscript.) de Quincey, C. (in press), Radical Nature: Consciousness all the way down. Vermont: The Marion Foundation. Edwards, M. & Bohm, D. (1991), Changing consciousness: Exploring the hidden sources of the social, political, and environmental crises facing our world. San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco. Elgin, D. (1993),The awakening earth: Exploring the evolution of human culture and consciousness. New York: William Morrow. Fichte, J. G. (1907), The science of ethics (trans. A. E. Kroeger). London, UK: Kegan Paul, Tranch, Trübner & Co. Forman, R. (ed.) (1990), The problem of pure consciousness: Mysticism and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. Foucault, M. (1970), The order of things: An archaeology of the human sciences (trans. Alan Sheridan). New York: Pantheon. Gerard, G. & Teurfs, L. (1994), The art and practice of dialogue. (12-tape audio course.) Laguna Hills, CA: The Dialogue Group. Güzeldere, G. (1995), Consciousness: What it is & how to study it. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(1), pp. 30-51. Habermas, J. (1984), The theory of communicative action. Vol. 1, London Heinemann; vol. 2. Cambridge: Polity. Habermas, J. (1990), The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Habermas, J. (1992), Postmetaphysical thinking. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ha'iri Yazdi, M. (1992), The principles of epistemology in Islamic philosophy: Knowledge by presence. Albany, NY: SUNY. Harman, W. & de Quincey, C. (1994), The scientific exploration of consciousness: Toward an adequate epistemology. Sausalito, CA: Institute of Noetic Sciences. Hartshorne, C. (1967), " Martin Buber's metaphysics. " In The philosophy of Martin Buber (eds. P. A. Schlipp & M. Friedman). La Salle, IL: Open Court. Hartshorne, C. (1991), The philosophy of Charles Hartshorne. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Hohengarten, M. (1992), in Habermas, J., Postmetaphysical thinking. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Holquist, M. (1990), Dialogism: Bakhtin and his world. New York: Routledge. Hunt, H. T. (1995), On the nature of consciousness: Cognitive, phenomenological , and transpersonal perspectives. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Hut, P. & Shepard, R. (1996), " Turning the hard problem upside down and sideways " . In Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4) 313-329. Jacques, F. (1991), Difference and subjectivity: Dialogue and personal identity (trans. Andrew Rothwell). New Haven: Yale University Press. James, W. (1977), " Radical empiricism " in The writings of William James: A comprehensive edition (ed. John McDermott). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Jaynes, J. (1976), The origins of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral mind. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin. Kant, I. (1961) The critique of pure reason. In W. Kaufmann, Philosophic classics: Bacon to Kant. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall. (Original German work (A) published 1781). (Second edition (B), published 1787). Kierkegaard, S. (1987), Either/or (trans. Hong & Hong) 2 vols. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Korten, D. (1995), When corporations ruled the world. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler. Laing, R. D. (1981), Self and other. London: Penguin. Levinas, E. (1969), Totality and infinity (trans. A. Lingis. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne. Levinas, E. (1981), Otherwise than being or beyond essence. (trans. A. Lingis). The Hague: Nijhoff. Marcel, G. (1967), " I and Thou. " In The philosophy of Martin Buber (eds. P. A. Schlipp & M. Friedman). La Salle, IL: Open Court. Macy, J. (1991), Mutual causality in Buddhism and general systems theory: The dharma of natural systems. Albany, NY: SUNY. Mead, G. H. (1967), Mind, self, & society: From the standpoint of a social behaviorist. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Mensch, J. R. (1988), Intersubjectivity and transcendental idealism. Albany, NY: (SUNY). Merrell-Wolff, F. (1983), The philosophy of consciousness without an object: Reflections on the nature of transcendental consciousness. New York: Julian Press. Morson G. S., & Emerson, C. (eds.) (1989), Rethinking Bakhtin: Extensions and challenges. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Mosès, S. (1992), System and revelation: The philosophy of Franz Rosenzweig (trans. Catherine Tihanyi). Detroit: Wayne State University Press. Nagel, T. (1979), Mortal questions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Natsoulas, T. (1981), Basic problems of consciousness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 132-78. Natsoulas, T. (1983), Concepts of consciousness. Journal of Mind and Behavior. 4, 13-59. Needleman, J. & de Quincey, C. (1993), " Questions of the heart: Inner empiricism as a way to a science of consciousness. " In Noetic Sciences Review, Summer, 26, 4-9. Onians, R. B. (1994), The origins of European thought about the body, the mind, the soul, the world, time, and fate. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Prabhu, J. (1997). Private communication. Rogers, C. (1951), Client-centered therapy. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Roszak, T. (1992), The voice of the earth. New York: Simon & Schuster. Russell, P. (1995), The global brain awakens: Our next evolutionary leap. Palo Alto, CA: Global Brain Inc. Sartre, J. P. (1960), The transcendence of the ego: An existentialist theory of consciousness. New York: Hill & Wang. Sartre, J. P. (1969), Being and nothingness (trans. H. E. Barnes). London: Methuen. Stolorow, R. D. & Atwood, G. E. (1992), Contexts of being: The intersubjective foundations of psychological life. New Jersey: Psychoanalytic Inquiry Book Series. Stolorow, R. D., Atwood, G. E., & Brandchaft, B. (eds) (1994), The intersubjective perspective. New Jersey: Jason Aranson. Tarnas, R (1991), The passion of the western mind: Understanding the ideas that have shaped our world view. New York: Harmony Books Taylor, C. (1989), Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Velmans, M. (1992), " Symposium: Consciousness and the physical world. " In Philosophical Psychology, 5(2), 155. Velmans, M. (1993), " A reflexive science of consciousness. " In Experimental and theoretical studies of consciousness. New York: John Wiley & Sons. Voloshinov, V. N. (1996), Marxism and the philosophy of language (trans. Ladislav Matejka & I. R. Titunik). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wheelwright, P. (1967), " Buber's philosophical anthropology. " In The philosophy of Martin Buber (eds. P. A. Schlipp & M. Friedman). La Salle, IL: Open Court. Whitehead, A. N. (1979), Process and reality: An essay in cosmology (Corrected edition, eds. D. R. Griffin & D. W. Sherburne). New York: The Free Press. (Original 1929). Whorf, B. L. (1956), Language, thought, and reality. New York: John Wiley & Sons. Wilber, K. (1995), Sex, ecology, spirituality: The spirit of evolution. Boston: Shambhala. Christian de Quincey, Ph. D., teaches philosophy of consciousness at John F. Kennedy University, and is managing editor of IONS Review. He is author of Radical Nature: Rediscovering the Soul of Matter (Invisible Cities Press, 2002), and co-author, with Willis Harman, of The Scientific Exploration of Consciousness: Toward an Adequate Epistemology. posted .b b.b. Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Recommended Posts
Join the conversation
You are posting as a guest. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.
Note: Your post will require moderator approval before it will be visible.