Guest guest Posted November 27, 2003 Report Share Posted November 27, 2003 Research Mon, 24 Nov 2003 10:54:20 -0500 [sSRI-Research] Book Review - Psychiatric Hegemony & the Manufacture of Mental Illness Book Review - Psychiatric Hegemony & the Manufacture of Mental Illness http://www.meresearch.org.uk/archive/skewed.html SKEWED: Psychiatric hegemony and the manufacture of mental illness in Multiple Chemical Sensitivity, Gulf War Syndrome, Myalgic Encephalomyelitis and Chronic Fatigue Syndrome Martin J. Walker ISBN 0-9519646-4-X Published by Slingshot Publications, BM Box 8314, London WC1N 3XX, England Cover price £12.00 Note from publisher: Cheques or postal orders must be sent with orders to Slingshot — no books can be sent out without payment. Campaigning groups who wish to raise money by selling the book, can contact Slingshot about receiving copies at very reduced rates. A press conference/launch is planned for December 2003 — for an invitation, contact Slingshot. The cover states: " SKEWED is a detailed investigation into the psychiatric diagnosis of a range of illnesses which some have suggested are actually caused by chemicals. The book traces the chemical companies' arguments against their products causing illnesses, and it tracks the growth of the theory promoted by them that individuals who report symptoms of chemically-induced ill health have personality disorders. The book asks how psychiatric theories of 'unexplained illness' have managed to gain ascendancy and shape the diagnosis, research funding, and public perception of these illnesses in Britain. " Martin J. Walker's last book was " Dirty Medicine " , described by Christopher Bird (author of The Secret Life of Plants) as " a masterpiece of investigative journalism and attentive scholarship, elegantly written. " Foreword Per Dalen, MD, PhD, Associate Professor of Psychiatry, University of Gothenburg, Sweden Medical culture is obsessed with mechanisms of disease, but actual causes are not a favourite topic. We don't know enough about causes to inspire the lay public and ourselves with confidence in our science by discussing them. Our lack of success in preventing many important diseases is of course largely due to ignorance. It is not uncommon for a medical scientist to mention an unsolved problem in terms like " the exact causes are not yet known, but… " The discussion is then usually moved to the safer ground of mechanisms. One tacit assumption is that we should first of all learn as much as possible about the many biochemical and physiological mechanisms that may be involved in the production of symptoms, autoimmunity for instance, or changes in neurotransmitter levels. With a more complete biological 'Meccano', it should be possible to build more and more comprehensive models of how various diseases develop. Will this automatically lead to causal understanding at the level where prevention becomes possible? Not necessarily, I am afraid. New causal knowledge may more often be found serendipitously and in other more direct and less time consuming ways than this inching along in the search for mechanisms. However, such a direct approach is usually not encouraged by the scientific community. There is an additional reason why mechanisms are important in medicine. When we draw the line between science and non-science in the health field, we usually exclude procedures and theories that cannot be understood in terms of accepted mechanisms. Homeopathy is a case in point. It doesn't really matter if it works in practice; its theory is utterly at odds with conventional medical thought. Any positive results in patients are simply explained as placebo effects. In this way knowledge of mechanisms becomes indispensable as a badge of scientific authority. My training in psychiatry started in the late 1950s, when neuroleptics and antidepressants were already available and the specialty was showing more scientific promise than ever before. Hysteria was something that neurologists encountered. Experienced psychiatists would tell stories of supposedly hysterical patients who had been referred back to their neurologists or internists without a psychiatric diagnosis, but with the suggestion that further investigation might be indicated — whereupon a brain tumour or some other serious illness was revealed. The average psychiatrist was then (and still is) fully occupied with patients whose histories and symptoms were predominantly psychiatric. The idea that large numbers of patients in general practice might need our attention for " medically unexplained symptoms " ' freely labelled as somatized, was simply unheard of. 'Somatization' is not a novel word. The oldest entry in the Oxford English Dictionary is from 1925 and shows that the origin of the word is in psychoanalysis: " conversion of emotional states into physical symptoms. " This is of course a sanitized version of the hysteria concept, a psychiatric diagnosis. Sigmund Freud put forward a number of psychological postulates styled as mechanisms that seeped into popular culture but were less successful in the medical field. Psychoanalysis is perhaps somewhat too speculative to mix well with ideas based on biology. Medicine has a kind of vigilance or " immune " system which resists intrusion of thoughts that fall short of a slightly pedantic standard of scientific credibility. The grapevine telegraph keeps us alert and updated. Inevitably though, there is no natural or manmade vigilance without blind spots. Emotional states can give rise to bodily symptoms; this is a matter of everyday experience. It is, however, deceptively easy to exaggerate the importance of this mind-body connection. The necessary question therefore becomes what, and how much can be reliably attributed to which emotional causes and for how long. This can only be answered from experience and common sense, since the actual mechanisms are very poorly understood and systematic clinical evidence is scarce. A generation ago physicians usually trusted their own clinical judgements, but in recent years the notion of " evidence based " medicine has altered this. We are now supposed to look for evidence, preferably statistical evidence, in the current literature. In some areas, such as somatization, there is simply no solid evidence, and yet the grapevine is silent about this. A vacuum is created where other forms of persuasion can find their way to the medical profession. It is interesting that another blind spot can be found in the area of placebo. Somatization and placebo are like the two sides of a coin. Both are believed to possess great power, the one of causing disease, the other of restoring health, Their mechanisms of operation are essentially unknown, and systematic studies have in fact yielded little or no evidence in clinical situations. There is no denying it; medicine uses a double standard in relation to scientific evidence. The placebo has been an integral part of our medical culture since the 1950s. Somatization gained prominence relatively recently. Scientific ideas normally have an interesting history, including a genealogy and a record of arguments pro and con. Important ideas rarely enter the scene fully fledged and unruffled by controversies, but somatization was presented even without a reference to psychoanalysis. Today we are sometimes told that somatization is the disease process to consider when physicians fail to explain the symptoms of the patient. The rather too flattering implication would be that medical science can now explain so many things that most of the remaining problems can be bundled together under a collective psychiatric label without further investigation. The truth, however, as we have seen, is that causal understanding is poorly developed. Explaining symptoms means something else here. When an officially accepted diagnosis has been found in a given case, for example, multiple sclerosis, the principal symptoms of the patient are seen as constituent parts of a familiar picture, and predictions can be made about prognosis, possible treatments can be chosen, et cetera. The physician is satisfied by this result, even though the cause of multiple sclerosis remains unknown, prevention is impossible, and treatments do not offer much hope of permanent recovery. An accepted diagnosis is not always enough, however. Recurrent or chronic low back pain is sometimes mentioned as a possible form of somatization. The reason for this is that most cases show no structural changes upon thorough investigation. Orthopaedic surgeons see innumerable patients with this very common affliction, and treatment results are poor. So why not call this a psychiatric problem? To my knowledge, psychiatry has never been officially or openly asked whether it is acceptable to use, or abuse, the concepts and tools of this specialty in new and unexpected ways. Psychiatrists tend to be hungry for acceptance by their non-psychiatric colleagues, and have not so far protested very audibly against what is going on under the label of somatization. GPs aided by psychologists skilled in cognitive behaviour therapy can apparently do the actual work with the patients. A major problem with the somatization approach is that its proponents take for granted that the causes of all those illnesses relabelled as psychiatric are psychological. In modern psychiatry the trend has long been in the opposite direction, away from the dogmatism once inspired by psychoanalysis. Classical psychiatric illnesses have unknown causes just as often as do somatic illnesses, and wholesale psychological explanations are increasingly a thing of the past. For some years now I have been convinced that the concept of somatization is being exploited for reasons that are only partly transparent. Scientifically there is no basis for the remarkable expansion of this field. The lives of large numbers of patients are touched and often made more difficult by what is going on. Psychiatry is apparently being abused, and it is, of course, very important to find out more about the background in order to do something about it. This is an area where concerned citizens have already begun to organise. In Skewed, Martin Walker investigates the vested interests involved in the problem of somatization and " unexplained illness " . On reading the manuscript, I found that viewing this apparently medical question from a sociological perspective gave me a new insight into this growing area of ostensibly psychiatric disorders. Readers who are not yet familiar with the tragic erosion of the truth-seeking scientific spirit in medical research will, I hope, also find this book an excellent introduction to these problems See also: " Dirty Medicine " by Martin J Walker http://www.sonic.net/kryptox/reviews3.htm#dirty -- " Mercury is a heavy metal that is very toxic even in small doses. Exposure to mercury can lead to damage of the brain, spinal cord, kidneys and liver. " The New York Times / May 7, 2003 http://www.nytimes.com/2003/05/07/international/asia/07INDI.html?ex==%1053316 & pagewanted====print & position Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Recommended Posts
Join the conversation
You are posting as a guest. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.
Note: Your post will require moderator approval before it will be visible.