Jump to content
IndiaDivine.org

Phenomenal Interview

Rate this topic


Guest guest

Recommended Posts

Guest guest

Please don't print this e-mail unless you really need to.

 

Beings are more than the sum of our economic appetites, and our country is more

than an economic machine.

-- Bill Moyers

For America's Sake

<

>

 

 

 

WHERE ANIMAL RIGHTS CAN GO FROM HERE

A Dialogue Between the Abolitionist Online and Lee Hall

 

Of the world's best-known animal advocacy groups, Friends of Animals has long

been the one that consistently advances the abolitionist paradigm. Lee Hall, a

vegan activist since 1983, has written and taught in the areas of immigration

and animal law, and became the legal director for Friends of Animals in 2002. In

addition to contributing to many paper and online publications, Lee authored the

entries on both vegetarianism and environmental justice for the Encyclopedia of

Activism and Social Justice (Sage, 2007), co-authored (with Priscilla Feral)

Dining With Friends: The Art of North American Vegan Cuisine, and most recently

penned Capers in the Churchyard: Animal Rights Advocacy in the Age of Terror.

Claudette Vaughan recently spoke with Lee for the Abolitionist-Online about this

new book, about the innovative advocacy style of Friends of Animals, and about

where the animal-rights movement can go from here.

 

________________________________

 

Abolitionist-Online: Thank you for writing the book Capers in the Churchyard:

Animal Rights Advocacy in the Age of Terror. It forced me to think and I believe

Jeffrey Masson, who wrote the Foreword, said much the same thing. Can I begin by

asking you to provide our readers an over-arching summary of your book?

 

Lee Hall: Much is said, Claudette, about whether adjustments in corporate

animal-husbandry methods can ever lead to the end of industries. As you know,

it's often called the rights-welfare debate: Some activists want to press

directly for animal rights; others want to push for reforms, commonly called

animal-welfare reforms, inside the industry where animals obviously lack rights.

To sharpen this debate, the book usually avoids the term welfare and talks of

husbandry when describing adjustments to the conditions inside the industries.

It's potentially confusing to call industrial adjustments " animal welfare "

provisions because attending to animals' welfare really isn't part of what

industry does.

 

Animal-rights activists should have nothing against true welfare; but do we work

out husbandry adjustments in the name of animal welfare? Within the use

structure, can any being's " welfare " seriously be advanced?

 

So first, let's disconnect animals' welfare, a word that commonly means well

being, from animal husbandry, a word that denotes manipulation. Next, I think we

can agree that providing for animal welfare is needed as long as domesticated or

dependent animals continue living here. Then let's get down to the nitty-gritty:

How do we work at the roots so that the need for this charity is relieved?

Advocacy's discourse needs to shift from dealing with, as farm campaigners put

it, the " 98% of animals with whom we interact " and start getting real about

ending these interactions.

 

Next, how does militant activism fit into this picture? I think it's just been

assumed that militancy signals radical beliefs, and that an animal-rights

lawyer's place is defending the positions of militants. I want to be clear here:

People should be defended; and I'm not justifying the government's crackdown on

dissent. I appreciate the lawyers who defend peoples' constitutional rights. Yet

for an animal-rights theorist, it's essential to ask: What is the vegan

position? What should an animal-rights theorist say about intimidation?

 

So I set out to explore this in depth. I found that militancy as a method or

policy within the animal-advocacy community is not aligned with rights-based

thinking. While the militant claims the goal justifies the means, rights

thinking questions that claim. Rights thinking doesn't hide its cards or permit

the exploitation of its principles. Veganism is based on non-violence, which

isn't just a tool to be used " tactically " or selectively -- any more than

veganism itself is.

 

Even on its own utilitarian terms, militancy is problematic for animal

advocates. In fact there are two major ways the animal users are able to manage

activists. The primary one is to negotiate animal-husbandry concessions; the

other is to portray activists as capable of using violence. Notably, militant

activism tends to focus on worst-treatment scenarios, just as mainstream

campaigns for husbandry reforms do.

 

The book's message to an abolitionist? Consider the possibility that militancy

undermines animal rights just as husbandry negotiations do -- on both the ethics

level and in actual results.

 

When reading Capers in the Churchyard, Lee, I sensed your concern that activists

using legal methods to get their animal-rights message across have been

demonized by the same broad stroke brush as others who use illegal means. Is

that correct?

 

Undoubtedly a conception was growing that animal activism equals intimidation or

chaos; some have an image of the activist community as being made up of

twenty-something-year-olds who are getting it out of their systems before

getting into the System, or simply maladjusted. So for example, some years back,

a school district moved to ban the word " vegan " from students' clothing as it

was thought to denote gang violence. Needless to say, it's absurd for a school

to ban the word " vegan " and laws are absurd when they attempt to scare us out of

using our rights to educate and associate. One can oppose absurd law yet also

comment on intimidation in activism. If students intimidate each other and

connect that conduct with veganism, if riot police are called to concerts, this

is what the public hears and peaceable vegans get lumped in with the toughs. The

problem isn't veganism, but that some people misappropriate the word.

 

The idea that one has to be willing to do something dangerous (and risk a lot of

money, given the restitution provisions) to be accepted into this or that scene

is also very troubling. We need to avoid isolating vegans into cliques that make

onlookers feel unwelcome or excluded.

 

Isn't it also fair to say in America the way to get rid of left-wing dissent is

by reductionist means? First start with the " obvious radicals " then it becomes

so reduced over time that anybody with an opposing view to industry and

government are deemed " violent radicals " -- which of course is untrue. In

" They'd Have Been Wise to Invent It: A Guide to 'Eco-Terror' Discourse, and the

Money Behind It

<http://www.friendsofanimals.org/actionline/fall-2006_07/They'd_Have_Been_Wise_T\

o_Invent_It.php> " you said much the same thing: " Increasingly, those who want

more than minor reforms can be equated with violent tendencies. " Please expand

your thoughts for us.

 

Yes, and the real irony here was that the founder of veganism saw it as the

essential peace movement. Does violence -- which makes expanding circles of

activists vulnerable to state control -- make sense as a method? Vegan Society

co-founder Donald Watson talked of " conscientious objection " both in its common

meaning and also in the context of ending humanity's war on other conscious

life. Abolitionism, in or out of the human context, will never be complete

without a successful peace movement that offers respect to all conscious life;

this was Watson's message. Watson was a straightforward thinker who spoke of

abolishing humanity's enslavement of all other animals whether for vivisection

or consumption or other uses, without hesitating to include birds, fish, worms,

bees. Without intimidation, Watson swiftly got the concept into leading

dictionaries, several languages, product symbols, and the consciousness of

millions of people who now live as abolitionists. That's direct action.

 

Everything we do in the movement has a teaching component. And young activists

shouldn't be wasted -- by spending their time persuading grocers and schools to

offer supposedly cage-free eggs, by risking jail, or both.

 

Activists should be aware of legal trends -- the effects of various activities

on criminal law. The book lays out these trends. But most of all it's asking

what message we want our lives to send to the world. We are only here for a

little while: What kind of humanity do we want to model? If the other animals

are ever going to have a chance, humanity must outgrow our domineering

tendencies. And it's important to show we can do it, just as it's important to

demonstrate that we can live and thrive on a non-violent diet.

 

Please say more for the Abolitionist-Online readers on the debate between

abolitionism and industry concessions. You are a well-known abolitionist,

lawyer, and feminist. In your own words please outline why campaigns for

industry reforms won't work.

 

Bringing feminism into the question is helpful, I think, because a key issue

addressed by feminism is hierarchy -- the systematic domination of some

identified group by those who benefit from that identification. Once that's seen

as the issue we face, things become clear. Does one demonstrate how to stop

dominating animals by asking for a better set-up at an egg farm? Clearly, no.

That's merely an adjustment within the domineering relationship, and is quickly

reduced to an argument over whose plan for the animals is best. One can only

relinquish the domineering relationship by deciding not to consume the chickens

or whatever's being taken from the chickens. Although we need not oppose

adjustments to industrial conditions, we work in a different sphere. Animal

rights, in our view, will be found on the tundra, in the forest, in the oceans,

streams, and sky. It will not be found in the shop, lab, factory or farm.

Handing authority to exploitive institutions in order to get respect for other

animals never did and still does not make sense. Radical (root) change will not

develop through a top-down approach, from corporations or lawmakers whose

economic interests are intertwined.

 

When our activists decline to follow the trend of constructing factory farming

campaigns or departments, this is precisely why. We assert that the customary

uses of nonhuman animals ought not be regulated, but ended. So our activism

doesn't seek out and reduce various painful methods of using other animals as

raw materials and killing them when their usefulness ends. We are here to offer

a positive vision: that other animals should be left free to experience their

lives --with all the pain and pleasure, autonomy and uncertainty, risks and

adventure that freedom involves. I work with Friends of Animals because that's

what the group stands for.

 

Why is this so unusual in the movement?

 

Perhaps, Claudette, people are attracted to animal advocacy precisely because

they so enjoy having, or interacting with, nonhuman animals. Yet an effective

animal-advocacy movement would continually question that same desire to have and

to interact.

 

Do you think that by bringing into the animal rights movement ex-vivisectors and

ex-animal control people, that their seemingly incapacity to work from a tabula

rasa situation has them reverting back to old ways and habits again, thus

watering down rights in favour of concessions?

 

It's certainly problematic if a vivisector or lab technician identifies with

advocacy yet still works in a lab (and let's count cognition labs; they're

invasive as any other). They're taking the insider's approach, which generally

boils down functioning as animal husbandry experts. But we all should

continually examine our lives and our thinking; no one works with a blank slate

who wasn't locked up throughout childhood. We're all responsible, as we're all

in the group of beings who've entitled ourselves to dominate, use, own, and kill

other animals. Humanity can be defined as the Owning Class.

 

Thus it's logical that we should cultivate a form of class consciousness in the

animal-rights movement. Activists who focus primarily on conditions miss the

point. They'll argue that a well-funded zoo or lab is a better place for animals

than a struggling refuge and they'll insist that the animals go to the zoo or

other institution -- agreeing with the parties who consider other animals

commodities, exhibits or instruments. You could say they've become class

collaborators. Progressives would get this point straight away if someone argued

to return human refugees to the control of those who enslaved them. Can't we

apply that consciousness beyond our own species? Send the apes to Chimp Haven;

Jane Goodall approves! So you have activists listening to people who think

government and industry know best. We need to cultivate a consciousness that

barely exists so far in the movement.

 

Whether to seek abolition or industry concessions is the debate the animal

rights movement had to have. Maybe just because of where the discussion is at

the moment, however, there's a simplistic tendency to equate legal activism with

concessions, and abolitionism with more militant tendencies -- or even, in the

U.S., equating abolition with sympathy towards militant actions from others.

 

That's why militancy should be examined in this same debate. I would say that

retaliatory activism has to be questioned just as husbandry negotiations do.

Until we actively confront domineering conduct and replace it with vegan

principles we'll have some activists canceling out the work of others without

the latter's consent.

 

Intimidation and veganism are not two prongs of the same movement. Intimidation

in the name of animal activism claims the goal justifies the means; whereas

vegan living sees the route and the goal as the same, and is conducive to animal

rights. Adding militancy to arguments over conditions doesn't transform those

arguments into animal-rights action.

 

From my experience as a grassroots activist, getting arrested in the battery hen

sheds en masse to expose conditions in a factory farm has always been treated as

a great threat to animal industry, government and the status quo, regardless of

who's doing it. Could this debate paralyze activists who have not really labeled

themselves either welfarists or abolitionists before -- and how do you think

this will play itself out in the political arena?

 

There's value in knowing what an egg farm is like, factory or free-range, which

is another form of factory. But people who consider themselves animal advocates

or vegetarians might still eat eggs and justify it by believing the conditions

are good. Explain that the small, idyllic pasture-based farm is thoroughly

exploitive, and the whole matter is addressed at once -- we're not just

critiquing the act of consuming high-volume, low-cost products. Donald Watson

grew up wanting to challenge the existence of the animal farm: not factory farms

-- which didn't exist in Watson's youth -- but the idyllic farm. It was an

uncle's country farm that Watson called Death Row. So why move the argument and

oppose the worst? If one opposes exploitation itself, the worst scenario is

encompassed in this broader argument. We get one chance to make a first

impression that illustrates our commitment to those for whom we advocate.

 

There's great promise in a mass gathering for a shared goal. But if that goal

could be read by the activists, industry, or the public as exposing the

conditions to be cleaned up in order for the products to be acceptable, then

there's all this great energy but corporations could turn it, martial-arts

style, to their own benefit. They've figured out there's money in adjusting the

conditions, substantial money.

 

In recent years, campaigners pursued celebrity chef Wolfgang Puck. Such activity

trades resources, years, activists, and money in exchange for public attention,

even if it doesn't incur mass arrests. This year, Puck did as the campaigners

asked. More public attention. Are the animals better off? Back in the 1980s,

veal was being renounced. The argument that ought to have arisen then, of

course, involved the dairy industry. But campaigners went in reverse and now

there's a market for " pink " or " rosé " veal; and where's the education about

dairy cows and how their calves will keep being born and sold for whatever price

the market will allow? By scoring a " victory " with Puck, campaigners perversely

bolstered a new market range.

 

And now, animal-husbandry investigations are being associated with animal

rights. After the group Mercy for Animals produced a videotape, Denny's

restaurant chain announced it would drop a supplier " accused of animal-rights

violations " against turkeys. As Mercy for Animals is " a voice for the rights of

all animals " , industry can assume they're scouting out animal-rights violations.

 

Also, the implication that we can somehow make farm animals comfortable bypasses

the reality that other animals -- those in their habitat, who otherwise could

live full and free lives -- are molested, displaced, and killed at the behest of

animal farming interests. In the U.S. , officials want to eradicate unowned pigs

because they could spread disease to commercially owned pigs. The same thing

with Ireland and Britain , wiping out badgers because they allegedly spread TB

to cows. Any sensible vegan could tell them the way to deal with TB in cattle is

to phase out cattle operations. Alas, animal advocates are so intensely focused

on the conditions in corporate buildings, whereas the badger's interest in

living is a true animal-rights issue. This underscores the holistic quality of

good vegan activism: Opt out of animal farming, and you simultaneously respect

the natural biocommunity. Animal agribusiness surely causes free-living animals

more grief than any other human practice.

 

I think advocates have got used to thinking that " incrementalist abolitionist

steps " actually can be found in the egg factory. Some abolitionist literature,

after all, has suggested as much. Let's consider a shift in linguistics, in our

theory, and in our real interventions. Animal rights can be meaningful only in

populations of animals where human dominion is not the paradigm. Free-range

concepts, alternatives to battery cages and all, if they really did make any

significant difference, would allocate still further space to human businesses.

Is that animal rights, or does it go in precisely the opposite direction?

 

The vegan's political strength is the same as the political strength of the

peace activist. As we've seen lately, if the peace movement allows its message

to be diluted, the military-industrial complex need not take it seriously.

Similarly, if activists aren't sure whether they can prevail, and thus find

value in compromise, they're absorbed into the dominant system. Industry will

suggest that earnest vegans are liabilities, then use the energy of the

compromisers to perpetuate its own success. And it will insist everyone had a

fair chance to dissent or to come to the table and iron out agreements. So let's

go back to the old yet profoundly important question: What if they held a war

and no one came? What if no one came to the war on other animals?

 

Bureaucratic groups addicted to wheeling and dealing over which animal products

should be approved by suppliers, retailers, and dining services aren't going to

convince us to barter away respect for other animals' most basic interests. Nor

can they ever put abolitionists into the margin of our own movement. So let's

stop seeing ourselves as marginal activists and know that abolitionism can and

does work. It works each time another person commits to vegan living. That's

direct politics. It will play out successfully if we want it.

 

It was extremely interesting to note in your " Guide to the 'Eco-Terror'

Discourse " that anti-environmental think tanks adamantly oppose strengthening

the Endangered Species Act.

 

The free-enterprise groups see other species as raw materials, and don't want

any of them getting uppity and trumping corporate interests.

 

Where there's pressure to have animals listed as imperiled due to global warming

-- melting ice caps, loss of coastal land -- free-enterprise proponents are

concerned that such legal moves would hamper corporate prerogatives to drill for

oil, expand airports, build resort hotels on sensitive habitat, log forests,

whatever they want to do to turn a profit. And inevitably, given the greenhouse

gas they create and the deforestation they cause, animal agribusinesses will

face increasing scrutiny. It's increasingly hard to avoid reality: Our planet is

mad as hell and would like to eject these companies.

 

If activists worked to strengthen the Endangered Species Act while concurrently

working to stop or at least severely limit breeders of " designer " and/or

" domestic " cats and dogs, has that the potential to save thousands of lives and

it's abolitionist even if it doesn't change the property paradigm. Your views,

Lee?

 

Lee Hall: I like where you're going here. The law resists taking away anything

from those at the top of the social hierarchy. So I think if we say it's morally

and ecologically important to respect free-living animals while putting a damper

on domestication, you have potential to do something that could work into a

challenge to the commodification of life.

 

A tension grows, of course, even as we talk about this. National economic growth

interests are ultimately represented in laws, in a world of several million

species and finite resources to share. The U.S. federal government is now

proposing to pass a general law that would undo any state laws of the types that

husbandry campaigners pour loads of donors' money into. (When will donors get

wise? Only when we vegans get through to them with the real message: Stop

funding endless adjustments in farming regulations that can be delayed for years

and then rescinded, and for heaven's sake eat something else!)

 

Yet unlike husbandry legislation, and unlike illusory protections for

domesticated animals who remain under human control, environmental protection

has abolitionist potential. Even if you do focus on the most endangered, there's

potential protection for an entire biocommunity -- the context in which

individual beings can exist. In Britain, the only wolves left are contained

within enclosures; were the big predators not deprived of their natural

existence, the integrity of the biocommunity could be respected, and perhaps in

the bargain we could stop thinking of humans who stalk other animals as though

they were doing something to restore balance. Insofar as we push

environmentalists to respect the ecology not for anthropocentric or national

interests, but because it is home to other beings whose lives depend on it, it

could be a good thing. It's got better potential than an effort to get

measurements into a statutory definition of " cage-free " eggs.

 

In her book Speciesism Joan Dunayer calls the Endangered Species Act speciesist

because it doesn't afford animals a right to exist as persons not inanimate

objects. What are your views?

 

Dunayer rightly notes that the Act deems conscious beings objects of trade,

valued merely on the basis of scarcity. It invokes their " aesthetic, ecological,

educational, historical, recreational, and scientific value " to us. Of those

values, the ecological and perhaps the historical values are more in touch with

the actual biocommunity than the rest, but these beings' inherent value goes

unmentioned. There are signs that priorities could change, if enough of us

insist. In the preface to the casebook Wildlife Law, professors Dale Goble and

Eric Freyfogle observe that environmental law, " once focused on direct threats

to human health, " now is also " concerned with assaults on non-human life. " This

suggests some willingness to perceive nonhuman animals as having value unto

themselves.

 

Law professor Catharine MacKinnon, in the 2004 essay " Of Mice and Men: A

Feminist Fragment on Animal Rights " , called for exactly that kind of discussion

in animal law, observing that the primary model of animal rights to date " misses

animals on their own terms. " It certainly does. But do we have standing to

complain that environmental law fails to acknowledge other animals on their own

terms when animal advocates themselves have yet to do so? Taking animals on

their terms would mean a momentous shift in the advocacy model -- a shift to

abolitionism.

 

There are many grand assumptions on what the law can accomplish for animals yet

when the mechanism of law is studied closely we find it less capable of ensuring

" rights " or even " justice " than protecting property. How will activists get the

paradigm shifted in law for animal rights, Lee?

 

Lee Hall: First, what do we mean when we say animal rights? Can we explain the

term in a way that most anyone could understand? This, perhaps, should be our

first mission. There's a little section in Capers called " the handy pull-out

guide to animal rights. " The point there isn't to be glib, but to say: Rather

than allow conventional legal thinking to shape our idea of what animal rights

is or isn't, we can express the positive essence of an idea and our commitment

to it.

 

Rights as we've known them come with an inherent dilemma: As you're suggesting,

Claudette, the institutions we call upon to formally extend them -- courts and

other legal authorities -- are the same ones that have systematically denied

them. And another thing. Rights theory is based on fairness, on treating similar

cases in similar ways, and therefore animals who are perceived as most similar

to current living persons under the law would get through the court's door

first. Even if apes are declared legal persons, others will have to wait. The

judicial route to fairness is long and resource-costly, and because it relies on

human concepts of similarity, it arguably relocates the border between persons

and nonpersons rather than blurring it. And this is why, while we do support

attempts to secure legal rights where they might be obtainable, we spend most of

our work educating about a vegan worldview, for each person who accepts this

view treats all conscious beings' interests with respect in an immediate way.

 

So we could see veganism as the do-it-yourself animal rights kit. No one needs

legal expertise or knowledge of hundreds of pages of theory to get the

incremental abolitionism moving. The North American Vegetarian Society's annual

Summerfest is vegan; increasingly we're seeing vegan events at sanctuaries and

shelters. In Britain and in pockets of other regions, feminists, gay youth

groups, peace camps, and many others have held fully vegan events.

 

Animal rights theorists have said that changes for animal rights will be

incremental but nobody is actually going into the specifics of it all. Say more

about the specifics.

 

Let's consider two different incremental efforts, one as the apex of the

pyramid, another one the broad base. The first seeks personhood for some groups

at a time; for example, it asks that nonhuman apes be understood as legal

persons with respected interests in their territory. As we've already noted,

there's value in a combined environmental and animal-rights focus. I think,

though, that the advocates pushing for this must envision it themselves if they

expect any national or international legal body to envision it. When asked about

a scenario where other animals are permitted to live in freedom in their own

territories, Peter Singer, president of the Great Ape Project, said:

 

Tragically, we've destroyed so much habitat that for some species, this is not a

great option. Chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas and orang-utans, for example, have

few safe havens now. So -- in the real world, anyway, rather than in some utopia

-- it might still be best for some species to live under human control and

protection.[1]

 

Recall that the nonhuman great apes are the beings thought, by Singer and

others, to have the strongest bid for rights under human law. But if " some

utopia " wherein their own connections and interests could truly be respected is

out of the question, then advocacy on their behalf equates to a call for certain

standards of human control. Sorry, animals, back to husbandry again. Is this

Animal Liberation or a page out of Orwell? If other apes must forever live under

" human control and protection " they become a permanent underclass. It seems that

humans are, in a sense, expecting to domesticate other apes. In our non-utopian

and very corporate world, advocacy is increasingly turning to view commercial

institutes as appropriate for other animals, apes included.

 

In short: Why ask for personhood if one is not willing to struggle for

territory? Anything else is just Personhood Lite.

 

Anyone can be pragmatic and tell us the habitat's practically gone and that life

is being commodified; I want to be surrounded by people who believe a world with

room for animal rights is a world that's still possible. Oscar Wilde said a map

that does not include Utopia isn't worth glancing at.

 

Few ape advocates have that map. Apes have been extended some measure of legal

respect in New Zealand , but no apes were being vivisected there. Let's consider

the United States , global leader in ape vivisection. The Chimpanzee Health,

Maintenance and Improvement Act, known as the CHIMP Act of 2000, condones

chimpanzee vivisection. Proponents of the Great Ape Project followed Jane

Goodall and supported it. When really tested, they condoned the legal

classification of nonhuman apes as appropriate research specimens. And even if

that weren't the case, in the United States the current makeup of the Supreme

Court would be an obstacle to nonhuman rights.

 

Even if the court idea were to work, we'd still need a vegan movement because

it's the only way we can address domestication. It makes no sense to go into

court and demand legal personhood for purpose-bred animals.

 

Thus, veganism is the broad-base approach to abolition. Though we don't know

what a court will decide, we can empower ourselves right now and model what a

human being would look like if animal rights were a reality -- by being vegan.

As the idea spreads, it incrementally abolishes exploitive industries. Depending

on our abilities, there are various ways to take these steps: We can set up a

speaking or leafleting event. We can get vegan cookbooks into our local library

or bookshop, and review pro-vegan books. We can convince a restaurant with a few

hold-out items, such as dairy desserts or cream, to become confidently vegan.

(Our New York office has had success with this.) We can pressure retirement

funds to divest from animal agribusiness. We can start a garden, or set up a

pool of buyers for a veganic grower. Encourage people to join a group that takes

veganism seriously. Link the group's website, and don't forget to include the

Vegan Organic Network.

 

You've mentioned your concerns about the Great Ape Project, with which, I

understand, you once volunteered. I see, though, that you do support the idea of

apes' personhood.

 

I support the removal of any conscious nonhumans from the category of property.

The effort must be careful, though, not to sell other animals down the river.

 

The Great Ape Project started in 1993 with the book The Great Ape Project:

Equality Beyond Humanity (Paola Cavalieri & Peter Singer eds.). It sparked hope

that people could broaden their definition of slavery and continue to work for

its abolition. An offshoot of the book was a volunteer-driven initiative called

GAP. Alas, its proponents didn't seem to attend to the logical conclusion of the

book's own thesis. Many have continued to cultivate an interest in exhibiting

nonhuman animals in homes, laboratories, and zoos or similar settings to

facilitate studies of language and other cognitive processes. In our view, it's

now obvious that these studies should be stopped. Further, the international

project has never offered a consensus that equality beyond humanity should

include all conscious beings.

 

The GRASP project at personhood.org, now under the auspices of Friends of

Animals, calls for a more inclusive reading of equality. It seeks legal rights

for all apes, great and small. Indeed we feel the time is ripe to be inclusive

of all primates given that a panel of 22 scientists, lawyers, and philosophers

in 2005 reported the results of a debate, continued for more than a year, over

the wisdom of inserting human stem cells into monkey brains, during which time

the team's scientists weren't sure how to ethically separate humans from other

primates <http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/8572943/> .

 

We'd be equally amenable to a case on personhood for burros or bats. We view all

conscious animal life as having interests relevant to that consciousness --

interests that should be respected. The popular agreement that apes have

cultures, however, highlights the point at which exclusive human personhood is

the most vulnerable to early change.

 

Some advocates dismiss the primates' rights effort as hierarchical thinking,

because it doesn't include all animals at once. In that respect, every example

of expanding legal rights to date has been imperfect. Today's human anti-slavery

movement doesn't include all animals at once. Should its activists stop their

work? If not, then why would any abolitionist ask people to stop working for the

extension of legal rights to nonhuman primates? That would itself be a species

bias. The critics could be right, Claudette, but I think they do need to be

prepared to answer such questions; so far, they haven't.

 

We're not naïve about this; we know that the use of nonhuman animals underlies

an enormous proportion of our current economic and social interactions. The law

will embrace a serious animal-rights concept only after a profound change in

humanity's worldview. A group that supports animal rights generally is in a good

position to make an argument for primates that doesn't set back the general

cause.

 

I think it was a huge mistake not to keep the " reverence for life " principle

that the animal rights movement represented originally and on that basis build

credibility needed for total no-kill solutions for all animals. Today's

campaigners seem fixated on animal death and slaughter techniques as part of an

over-all campaign " for " animals, to help " reduce " their suffering. Did you know

it's come to light that PETA, for example, installed a walk-in refrigerator on

their property to store dead bodies of animals, and that their " Community Animal

Project " means contracting with a crematorium? This came to light after dozens

of homeless animals were discovered dumped in a dumpster by PETA staffers, after

these staffers were sent out by PETA headquarters and assigned to take animals

from a North Carolina shelter.

 

It is open knowledge that the group carries out killing (one of the most

disrespectful customs is the use of the term 'euthanasia' for mass killing) and

that they've done so for a long time. The group leaders acknowledge this. So

advocates generally know killing goes on, bodies are stored, and so forth. Why

is this tolerated? Killing is not advocacy. If a group of people goes about

systematically rounding up cats and dogs to kill them, that group should not

identify itself with animal rights. It should be straightforward enough to call

itself an animal-control agency.

 

We're told that institutional killing is needed because the burden is simply too

heavy for no-kill shelters. I know well-meaning people believe this. Indeed,

no-kill shelters acknowledge that they are overburdened, and that resources fall

short. But wouldn't the logical response involve more of the resource-rich

groups endorsing and supporting no-kill shelters and private sanctuaries?

Describing the no-kill idea as unworkable only adds to the pressure faced by

private refuges, true shelters, and supporters of decent proposals such as

trap-neuter-return. And the killing functions as a key part of the cycle that

facilitates the breeding of pets.

 

In my view the trouble lies with the bureaucracy of mainstream advocacy.

Foucault was expert at recognising how such systems are at fault. Notice how

badly the animal rescue side of mainstream animal advocacy is treated by its

often-rich bureaucratic side. I wonder why this is and what your thoughts on the

matter are.

 

Adding up the members and money won't tell you how principled a group is or how

successful it is in changing humanity's attitudes about the inherent value of

other animals. Becoming large often means losing touch with places and issues

outside the offices. A sad result is the way small pockets of feral cat advocacy

(those who endorse neutering, not killing) and true shelters and refuges are

abandoned, isolated, told their work is in vain.

 

Obviously I do see value in having an organizational base for change. Some of us

have attempted working independently for years, lighting our own small fires,

sending up our signals, waving our torches, but the wind can quickly blow these

out. We are, after all, living in a world where major issues play out on a

global scale. Today's activists must confront cloning and biotech, climate

change, anti-terrorism laws and the global prison-industrial complex. And

although I know the power of a few people of integrity -- thanks to an

independent activist I became a vegan -- sometimes you do need to be able to put

together high-quality reports to get policy changed; you need resources to keep

a refuge afloat or to sponsor festivals and back the grassroots efforts. We're

working to pull together some of the best community initiatives, and not fall

into the model of growing a brand name rather than a movement. This is not a

platitude. If a group declines to go along with the predominant bureaucratic

model, it's surely no path of least resistance, but an element of activism in

itself.

 

Returning to " Capers in the Churchyard " , you have explained why you think

violence jeopardizes what the animal rights movement originally set out to

accomplish: win the hearts and minds of a critical mass of people, change their

eating habits over to plant-based solutions and change the law to make animals

" persons " not things. Can I ask you this? What do you say when people ask you

how activists can change the face of the monolithic food industry non-violently?

 

Lee Hall: I'm surprised that anyone would think activists could change the

monolithic food industry violently. Commercial interests have the state's

tremendous coercive authority at their disposal, and violence immediately makes

activists vulnerable to that authority. That's why investigators plant people in

a community to stir up militant actions; and if an action can't be distinguished

from that of an agent provocateur, it's probably a bad idea.

 

And although the food industry shapes demand, consumers can exert influence by

opting out of animal products, by forming and relying on vegan initiatives.

Vegans can't seriously be dismissed as people out to threaten livelihoods when

they're really asking to reroute human energy to ethical living in place of

uncaring businesses that are often as inhospitable to their workers as they are

to the planet and its life in general. The situation of workers too would vastly

improve in a culture that values the ecology and peaceable, meaningful work. So

prevailing over the food industry requires neither concessions nor fighting; it

means growing a numerically significant vegan movement. And in 24 years of

activism I haven't met a single vegan who reports having been intimidated into

it.

 

I recently spoke with people who gathered for a vegan meal and talk at a

college. One participant repeatedly argued the militancy point. I understood the

sincerity of the speaker, and discussed the various objections posed. We went on

like this for several minutes. Eventually, the person just exclaimed: " Well,

yes, it IS war! Humanity is NEVER going to be respectful to animals voluntarily

-- human nature just isn't like that! "

 

Veganism was quite clearly based on the idea that that peace is possible. We get

out of bed each day and resolve to be optimists. It's mainly because we think

there's no point, as the apt saying goes, in being anything else.

 

There are 3 viewpoints on political violence that you didn't mention and I

wonder if you would have a look at them here. Number one: The New World Order

needs conflict to operate; it needs the " good guys " fighting the villains,

bringing democracy and " peace " to the world in a legal sense while they

themselves use pre-emption and all kinds of illegal tactics to get precisely

what they want. We know through reading your " Guide to 'Eco-Terror' Discourse,

and the Money Behind It " and Robert F. Kennedy's Crimes Against Nature: Standing

Up to Bush and the Kyoto Killers Who Are Cashing In on Our World where real

violence lies, where the deals are struck. By naming a few animal and eco

activists, does your book play into the hands of these people thus allowing

circumstances to scapegoat (is there a better, non-speciesist word for

" scapegoat? " ) a few vocal and militant animal activists?

 

Yes, there are levels of coercion, and we should keep the effects of militancy

in perspective. Still, the question is whether people -- and no person is

insignificant -- want to emulate that New World Order or cultivate alternatives.

We have activists saying the state does such-and-such so activists should fight

on those terms; we have activists saying there's going to be collateral damage

or that targeting non-combatants could be a viable tactic. I'm commenting on

people who are already highly public with their views. Clever critics will focus

on the violent rhetoric, shifting public attention to a few people or even a few

lines in a speech. The focus should be instead on the cloning, GMOs, pesticides,

global warming, ecological refugees, mass extinctions.

 

The urge to create " soldiers " and " heroes " focuses on human personalities. The

hierarchy that's established this way is minor in the grand scheme, yet quite

assertive within activist communities. Young idealists are disabled by fines,

restitution orders, prison terms, authorities who want to collar " terrorists " ,

and massive peer pressure. The pressure on young people to take forcible action

also echoes the way national wars are handled, where the older people often

advance the justifications and the younger ones are sacrificed.

 

Have young militants a clear idea of the goals of the animal-rights position

when this happens? The guidelines and the spokespeople they follow strongly

suggest otherwise. The book gets into that in a detailed way. For now I'll just

note that violence is the norm in our culture and has been justified as noble

for thousands of years. The idea that intimidation or destruction is

revolutionary ignores the key reality that they're really the status quo. I

think that's what John Lennon meant, pointing out that revolution should be

disconnected from destruction.

 

A second thesis on violence your book didn't mention: In any " new " revolutionary

movement the direct action aspect usually takes around 15 years to either

produce a good result or degenerate into thuggery. It either works in that time

frame or it has to reemerge further down the track, reinstigated and reenergised

by new blood. In our era we have seen it work in some instances and fail

miserably in others. My own opinion is it worked against apartheid in South

Africa (Nelson Mandela's No Easy Walk to Freedom, chapter 7: Our Struggle Needs

Many Tactics) and it failed miserably with the tactics of the modern IRA of

today.

 

The book regards veganism as an ethical case for peaceful conduct. A vegan

culture would not be imposing itself violently on another culture and

subjugating people in the first place; Donald Watson envisioned it as the first

civilization that really merits that name.

 

It's hard to say what did or didn't overcome subjugation when resistance has

included a variety of tactics. To my mind, the historical timeline suggests

massive international support, songs, strikes and boycotts forced apartheid to

crumble. We can't prove that definitively; as a scientist would say, there was

no control group. But refocus the question: Veganism isn't about choosing

between two reactions to repression. That's what proponents of peace are so

often asked: " But what would you do in the situation where [fill in a grotesque

example from history]? " Now if one says that the oppressed group should have

responded differently when faced with terrible pain, their children dying or

sold out from under them, one's argument can be heard as insultingly simplistic.

The book asks a question about social change at a deeper level: How should we

consciously act so as to avert these atrocities in the first place?

 

In the animal-rights movement, the oppressed can't free themselves from

systematic domination; they rely fully on the controlling class to change things

at every phase of the movement. It's critical, then, to strive to present ideas

so reasonable minds can understand and accept them. People might say

non-violence is a luxury, and, acknowledging my own privilege, I've given that

objection serious consideration -- and I've come to the view, Claudette, that

waving off what people think is self-indulgence. If we are serious about

organizing for power, we've got to reach out to the progressive element in the

media and in every community.

 

One of the strongest dissenters we have is Michael Berg, parent of Nick Berg, a

U.S. civilian abducted in 2004, reportedly to avenge the Abu Ghraib detainees.

Last year, when the al-Qaeda leader who presumably beheaded Nick was killed,

Michael Berg refused to rejoice. " As long as people use violence to combat

violence, " said Berg, " We will always have violence. " It's clear that this stand

is no luxury: Berg's been threatened and shot at. Berg still wants justice, but

of the restorative kind. So, for example, the one who wielded the knife, instead

of being overpowered and destroyed, would work off this terrible debt and regain

personal integrity by caring for amputees. You and I -- and Michael Berg too,

who's vegan -- work in the animal-rights movement because we want to bring

ourselves to restorative justice. We'll be doing this throughout our lives,

don't you think? I'm not endorsing guilt; the point is to take responsibility.

We hope others, those who are still profiting from exploitation, will follow us

in this. We can guide them, but attacking them doesn't invite them into the

movement.

 

As for the idea that some are evil and deserve violent retribution, perhaps it's

a good idea to stand back and ask who is in the position to cast stones.

Militant activists have family members, teachers, friends at school who eat

pizza or drink coffee with cream or buy substances that were tested on animals.

If the activists followed the logic of retribution, they'd be clubbing their

parents. That's not an option so the target is the experimenter or some stranger

-- someone defined as cruel or evil, an enemy, scum. It's the minority of young

people who have a vivisector in the family but nearly everyone is surrounded by

people going to the local Safeway. We are all in the class that has benefited

from the oppression of other animals. Our work is to bring us all to a better

way of thinking.

 

A final specific of violence not mentioned in your book: People of non-violence

die violently for political reasons and this is no strange coincidence. In my

view, the assassination attempt of Pope John Paul 11 and the assassination of

John Lennon ( " Give Peace A Chance " ) could suggest that these people are more of

a threat to those running the existing violent order than Bin Laden could ever

hope to be because Bin Laden is providing them with the " bad guy " scenario

needed so desperately to keep plundering the world's resources. I know you have

said in your writings, Lee, that non-violence is more revolutionary than

violence, but you didn't say that non-violence is not required in the New World

Order's world to accomplish their aims and agenda, and thus this is the

" revolutionary " nature of non-violence. Conspicuous by its absence.

 

Recall Lennon and Ono's " Imagine " : No countries, nothing to kill or die for.

Imagine the idea spreading, not just in religious circles, but everywhere, that

we don't return violence with violence. The nation is out of its league in this

idea, an idea that has inspired some of the most profound activism and art. No

countries, no borders, no nationalism -- a truly liberating thought and one

we've been carefully trained to avoid and fear, as it calls into question the

state's very existence and our licence to kill. Apart from our agreement to

acknowledge it, the country doesn't exist. Imagine we all stop believing the

leaders who want us to see the country as a reality, and war as natural and

eternal.

 

The status quo isn't our fate. It's held together when everyone does as we're

told. We have the power; the state merely has authority, which is a far weaker

thing, because authority is the artificial kind of power that's backed by

violence. One thing small children know instinctively is that a parent who

resorts to hitting has lost the argument. I'd prefer not to live in a world

that's controlled by a violent parent or anyone who follows that model. I have

no intention of following such leaders -- on any scale.

 

We need a general paradigm shift, the commitment of critical numbers of the

populace to change because a critical number of us want to change, because it's

right and reasonable and the ethical thing to do, and a key move to the only

really sustainable way of living on this planet.

 

1 Quoted in Rosamund Raha, " Animal Liberation: An Interview with Peter Singer "

in The Vegan (Autumn 2006).

 

 

Veronika Terrian

 

Happiness is when what you think, what you say, and what you do are in harmony.

We must be the change that we wish to see, not the darkness we wish to leave

behind. *Mahatma Gandhi

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Join the conversation

You are posting as a guest. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.
Note: Your post will require moderator approval before it will be visible.

Guest
Reply to this topic...

×   Pasted as rich text.   Paste as plain text instead

  Only 75 emoji are allowed.

×   Your link has been automatically embedded.   Display as a link instead

×   Your previous content has been restored.   Clear editor

×   You cannot paste images directly. Upload or insert images from URL.

Loading...
×
×
  • Create New...